False necessity: Difference between revisions

Content deleted Content added
m →‎Background: minor fixes, mostly disambig links, replaced: SchellingSchelling using AWB
Very bad editorializing and OR. Trying to fix the worst. Other minor changes.
Line 1:
{{refimprove|date=June 2012}}
'''False necessity,''' or "anti-necessitarian social theory," is a contemporary social theory that champions the plasticity of society and the unlimited potential for transformation. It is foremost a critique of necessitarian thought in conventional social theory, which holds that parts of the social order are necessary and the result of the natural flow of history, e.g. [[liberalism]] or [[Marxism]]. It develops a full attack on the idea that human societies must be organized in a certain way, e.g. [[liberal democracy]], and that human activity will adhere to certain forms, e.g. [[homo economicus]]. As a theory, ''false necessity'' embraces deep-structure analysis to understand socio-political arrangements, but discards the tendency to assemble indivisible categories and to create law-like explanations. In action, it aims to liberates human activity from necessary arrangements and limitations, and to open up a world without constraints where the possible becomes actual.
 
'''False necessity,''' or "anti-necessitarian social theory," is a contemporary [[social theory]] thatwhich championsholds thethat plasticity[[society]] ofis societyplastic and thecan unlimitedchange potentialin forunlimited transformationways. It is foremostin acontrast critique ofto necessitarian thought in conventional social theory (e.g. [[liberalism]] or [[Marxism]]), which holds that parts of the social order are necessary and the result of the natural flow of history, e.g. [[liberalism]] or [[Marxism]]. It develops a full attack onopposes the idea that human societies must be organized in a certain way, e.g. [[liberal democracy]], andor that human activity willalways adhere tofollows certain formspatterns, e.g. [[homo economicus]]. As a theory, ''false necessity'' embracesuses deep-structure analysis to understand socio-political arrangements, but discardsdoes thenot tendency to assemblecreate indivisible categories andor to create law-likerigid explanations. In action, itIt aims to liberates human activity from necessary arrangements and limitations, and to open up a world withoutremove constraints whereon thehuman possibleactivity.{{Citation becomesneeded|June actual.2012}}
Contemporary political thinkers and philosophers have championed ''false necessity.'' [[Roberto Mangabeira Unger]] has employed the theory most forcefully in developing social, political, and economic alternatives,<ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''Democracy realized: the progressive alternative.'' London: Verso, 1998</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''Free trade reimagined: the world division of labor and the method of economics.'' Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''The future of American progressivism: an initiative for political and economic reform.'' Boston: Beacon Press, 1998</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''The left alternative.'' London: Verso, 2009.</ref> as well as in his political activism and appointments in Brazilian politics.<ref>{{cite web|last=Press|first=Eyal|title=The Passion of Roberto Unger|url=http://linguafranca.mirror.theinfo.org/9903/unger.html|publisher=Lingua Franca|accessdate=4 July 2011|month=March|year=1999}}</ref><ref>{{cite news | last = Barrionuevo | first = Alexei | title = ‘Minister of Ideas’ Tries to Put Brazil's Future in Focus | publisher = [[The New York Times]] | date = 2008-02-02 | url = http://www.nytimes.com/2008/02/02/world/americas/02unger.html?_r=2&ref=world&oref=slogin&oref=slogin | accessdate = 2008-02-02}}</ref> [[Richard Rorty]] compared the theory's move towards greater liberalism with [[Jürgen Habermas]], and called it a powerful alternative to the postmodern "[[School of Resentment]]."<ref>Rorty, Richard. “Unger, Castoriadis, and the Romance of a National Future.” ''Northwestern University Law Review'' 82 (1988 1987).</ref> Other thinkers have said the theory is "a challenge that the social disciplines can ignore only at their peril."<ref>Trubek, David M. “Radical Theory and Programmatic Thought.” ''American Journal of Sociology'' 95, no. 2 (1989): 447.</ref> [[Bernard Yack]] wrote that it contributed to "a new left Kantian approach to the problem of realizing human freedom in our social institutions."<ref>Yack, Bernard. “Review: Toward a Free Marketplace of Social Institutions: Roberto Unger’s ‘Super-Liberal’ Theory of Emancipation.” ''Harvard Law Review'' 101, no. 8 (June 1, 1988): 1973.</ref>
 
Contemporary political thinkers and philosophers have championed ''false necessity.'' [[Roberto Mangabeira Unger]] has employed the theory most forcefully in developing social, political, and economic alternatives,<ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''Democracy realized: the progressive alternative.'' London: Verso, 1998</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''Free trade reimagined: the world division of labor and the method of economics.'' Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''The future of American progressivism: an initiative for political and economic reform.'' Boston: Beacon Press, 1998</ref><ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira. ''The left alternative.'' London: Verso, 2009.</ref> as well as in his political activism and appointments in Brazilian politics.<ref>{{cite web|last=Press|first=Eyal|title=The Passion of Roberto Unger|url=http://linguafranca.mirror.theinfo.org/9903/unger.html|publisher=Lingua Franca|accessdate=4 July 2011|month=March|year=1999}}</ref><ref>{{cite news | last = Barrionuevo | first = Alexei | title = ‘Minister of Ideas’ Tries to Put Brazil's Future in Focus | publisher = [[The New York Times]] | date = 2008-02-02 | url = http://www.nytimes.com/2008/02/02/world/americas/02unger.html?_r=2&ref=world&oref=slogin&oref=slogin | accessdate = 2008-02-02}}</ref> [[Richard Rorty]] compared the theory's move towards greater liberalism with [[Jürgen Habermas]], and called it a powerful alternative to the postmodern "[[School of Resentment]]."<ref>Rorty, Richard. “Unger, Castoriadis, and the Romance of a National Future.” ''Northwestern University Law Review'' 82 (1988 1987).</ref> Other thinkers have said the theory is "a challenge that the social disciplines can ignore only at their peril."<ref>Trubek, David M. “Radical Theory and Programmatic Thought.” ''American Journal of Sociology'' 95, no. 2 (1989): 447.</ref> [[Bernard Yack]] wrote that it contributed to "a new left Kantian approach to the problem of realizing human freedom in our social institutions."<ref>Yack, Bernard. “Review: Toward a Free Marketplace of Social Institutions: Roberto Unger’s ‘Super-Liberal’ Theory of Emancipation.” ''Harvard Law Review'' 101, no. 8 (June 1, 1988): 1973.</ref>
 
 
==Background==
Modern social theory is haunted by a tension between the realization of human freedom and the necessity of a social context.<ref>This background is drawn from Ian Shapiro, “Review: Constructing Politics,” Political Theory 17, no. 3 (1989): 475-482, Roberto Mangabeira Unger, ''Social Theory: Its Situation and its Task, Politics 2'' (New York: Verso, 1987), Bernard Yack, ''The longing for total revolution: philosophic sources of social discontent from Rousseau to Marx and Nietzsche'' (Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press, 1986), Bernard Yack, “Review: Toward a Free Marketplace of Social Institutions: Roberto Unger’s ‘Super-Liberal’ Theory of Emancipation,” Harvard Law Review 101, no. 8 (June 1, 1988): 1961-1977.
</ref> Liberal political theorists of the seventeenth century, such as [[Hobbes]] and [[John Locke|Locke]], saw the issue as one of sacrificing some individual freedoms in order to gain others. They understood social context as an enabling constraint--a necessary imposition that limited activity in some spheres in order to expand it in others. (Good examples of this might be language, which limits certain expressions while also providing the very conduit by which to make them; or traffic laws, which compel us to drive on one side of the road but make possible the ability to travel more freely than if we were constantly assailed by oncoming traffic.) In the socio-political realm, these early liberal thinkers argued that we agree to surrender our freedom for political authority in order to gain greater freedom from a [[state of nature]]. The sovereign authority is a constraint, but it allows freedom from the constraint that other individuals might impose upon us. In this way, context is always seen as a means of increasing freedom rather than rescinding it.
 
==Background==
These early [[Age of Enlightenment#Important intellectuals|Enlightenment thinkers]] did much to break down the notion that religious, aristocratic, or absolutist institutions and organizations represented the natural state of the world. What these thinkers did not do, was confirm the absolute freedom of the individual as liberated from any type of constraining context. They had shown that there are necessary contexts placed upon our selves and our activity, and while this might embody a rejection of aristocratic privilege or monarchical domination, it did not liberate humanity from social necessity. Furthermore, such ideas only worked to entrench domination by giving license for some to rule and others to be ruled.
Modern social theory is haunted bycontains a tension between the realization of human freedom and the necessity of a social context.<ref>This background is drawn from Ian Shapiro, “Review: Constructing Politics,” Political Theory 17, no. 3 (1989): 475-482, Roberto Mangabeira Unger, ''Social Theory: Its Situation and its Task, Politics 2'' (New York: Verso, 1987), Bernard Yack, ''The longing for total revolution: philosophic sources of social discontent from Rousseau to Marx and Nietzsche'' (Princeton, N.J: Princeton University Press, 1986), Bernard Yack, “Review: Toward a Free Marketplace of Social Institutions: Roberto Unger’s ‘Super-Liberal’ Theory of Emancipation,” Harvard Law Review 101, no. 8 (June 1, 1988): 1961-1977.
</ref> LiberalSome political theorists of the seventeenth century, such as [[Hobbes]] and [[John Locke|Locke]], saw the issue as one of sacrificing some individual freedoms in order to gain others. They understood social context as an enabling constraint--a necessary imposition that limited activity in some spheres in order to expand it in others. (GoodFor examples of this might be languageexample, which limits certain expressions while also providing the very conduit by which to make them; or traffic laws, which compel us to drive on one side of the road but makeallow possible the abilityus to travel more freely than if we were constantly assailed by oncoming traffic.) In the socio-political realm, these early liberal thinkers argued that we agree to surrender our freedom for political authority in order to gain greater freedom from a [[state of nature]]. The sovereign authority is a constraint, but it allows freedom from the constraintconstraints that other individuals might impose upon us. In this way, context is always seen as a means of increasing freedom rather than rescinding it.{{Citation needed|June 2012}}
 
These early [[Age of Enlightenment#Important intellectuals|Enlightenment thinkers]] did much to break downopposed the notion that religious, aristocratic, or absolutist institutions and organizations represented the natural state of the world. WhatHowever, these thinkersthey did not do,argue was confirmfor the absolute freedom of the individual as liberated fromwithout any type of constraining context. They had shown that there are necessary contexts placed upon our selves and our activity, and whilesaid thisthat mighthumans embodywere astill rejectionsubject of aristocratic privilege or monarchical domination, it did not liberate humanity fromto social necessity. Furthermore, such ideas only worked to entrench domination by giving license for some to rule and others to be ruled.
Inspired by [[Kant]]'s thesis of [[Kant#Idea of freedom|human freedom]], which argued that there is no evidence to disprove our absolute freedom or capacity to resist external domination, thinkers at the end of the eighteenth century addressed how human freedoms were constrained by social institutions. Thinkers like [[Fichte]], [[Schiller]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]], and [[Hegel]] argued that those institutions that constrain human freedom and subject the individual to fear and prejudice insult human dignity and deny the individual his autonomy. They thus sought to transform the external constraints of social institutions into something that would embody freedom from necessity. They sought to overcome the dehumanization of the world--one that stripped us of our humanity--caused by our failure to realize our own humanity and the essence of the human being.
 
Inspired by [[Kant]]'s thesis of [[Kant#Idea of freedom|human freedom]], which argued that there is no evidence to disprove our absolute freedom or capacity to resist external domination, thinkers at the end of the eighteenth century addressed how human freedoms were constrained by social institutions. Thinkers like [[Fichte]], [[Schiller]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]], and [[Hegel]] argued that those institutions that constrain human freedom and subject the individual to fear and prejudice insult human dignity and deny the individual his autonomy.{{Citation needed|June 2012}} They thus sought to transformchange the external constraints of social institutions intoto something that would embodyallow freedom from necessity.{{Citation They sought to overcome the dehumanization of the world--one that stripped us of our humanity--caused by our failure to realize our own humanity and the essence of the human being.needed|June 2012}}
Coupled with these Enlightenment thinkers' ideal of human freedom was the aspiration for universal law. Thinkers aimed to liberate humanity from the chains of social necessity, and to also put in place the structures to allow each to realize his own freedom. But they worked to do so deterministically. Marx, for example, for all his efforts of human liberation from domination, still put us at the mercy of historical and institutional necessity. Although modern social theory was born out of the rejection of naturalism and social necessity, the rebellion was only half complete.
 
Coupled with theseThese Enlightenment thinkers' ideal of human freedom was the aspiration for universal law. Thinkersalso aimed to liberate humanity from the chains of social necessity, and to also put in place the structures to allow each to realize his or her own freedom. But they worked to do so deterministically. Marx, forFor example, forwhile allMarx hisopposed effortsdomination ofby humanothers, liberation from domination,he still put us at the mercy ofsupported historical and institutional necessity. AlthoughThe modern socialcontemporary theory wasof born''false outnecessity'' ofgoes thefurther rejectionthan ofthis, naturalismsaying andthat social necessity,placticity themeans rebellionthat washuman onlyfreedom halfis unrelated to social context or historical completetrajectory.
The contemporary theory of ''false necessity'' attempts to realize this idea in its entirety, and to escape the limitations of liberal and Marxist theories. It aims to realize social placticity by decoupling human freedom from any necessary social context or historical trajectory. The theory recognizes the need for social context, but also affirms the human potential to transcend any context. We need not be constrained by any structure.
 
==The Theorytheory of ''Falsefalse Necessity''necessity==
TheImportant theoryparts inof itsthe full expressiontheory isare credited to Harvard law faculty and social theorist [[Roberto Mangabeira Unger]]. His main book on the thesis, ''False Necessity: Anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy,'' was first published in 1987 by Cambridge University Press, and reissued in 2004 by Verso with a new 124 page introduction, and a new appendix, "Five theses on the relation of religion to politics, illustrated by allusions to Brazilian experience."<ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira, ''False necessity: anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy: from Politics, a work in constructive social theory,'' second edition (London: Verso, 2004).</ref>
 
The theory of ''false necessity'' developsattempts anto understandingunderstand of human beingshumans and ourhuman history without making ourselves the object of a law-giving fate. It rejects the assumption that certain and necessary laws of organization and change govern the social, political, and economic institutions of human activity and thereby limit human freedom. It points outholds that the problem with traditional deep structure theory, such as Marxism, is that it couples the distinction of deep structure and routine practice with both indivisible types of social organization, and deep seated constraints and developmental laws. ByThe embracingtheory the former and discardingrejects the laterconstraints, the theoryand focuses on an analysis of how human behavior is shaped by the deep structures of these institutions, and thathow they can be remade at will, either in whole or in part. The aim is to rescue social theory and recreate the project of self affirmation and society.<ref name= "fn xvii">Unger, Robero Mangabeira, ''False necessity: anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy: from Politics, a work in constructive social theory'' (London: Verso, 2004), xvii.</ref>
 
Rather than "enabling constraint" or "universal structure," the theory advocates "structure-denying structures" -- that is, structures that enable their own dissolution and remaking. ThisSince wouldthese increasestructures ournormally freedomconstrain byour looseningactivities, thethis holdwould onincrease theour activitiesfreedom.{{Citation thatneeded|June those structures govern.2012}}
 
==Sources of Entrapmententrapment and Emancipationemancipation==
The problem of false necessity arises due to the failure of transformative practice to realize its stated aim. This can take form in three different scenarios:<ref name="Social Theory 5">Unger, Roberto Mangabeira, ''Social Theory: Its Situation and its Task, Politics 2'' (New York: Verso, 1987), chapter 5.</ref>
*the ideals fought for (democracy, decentralization, technical coordination, etc.) result in the development of rigid institutions
Line 30:
*the survival effect in which there is a fear of disturbance of contemporary arrangements.
 
Unger points to mass politics as a means to counter oligarchy and group identity. However, as long asif these forms are only disturbed and not destroyed, democracy is limited and becomes a quarrel about forms of power and seizing advantage advantage. Likewise, enlarged economic rationality provides another source of emancipation by shifting economic and social relations in the ability to constantly innovate and renew.<ref name="Social Theory 5"/>
 
==The Radicalradical Projectproject==
The theory of ''false necessity'' carriesstrongly to the hiltsupports the idea that the organization of society is made and can be remade—weremade can rebelwe againstcan remake the worldssociety we have built; wein cana interrupt our rebellions and establish ourselves in anyform of thoseour worldschoosing. By emphasizing the disembodiment of institutional and social structures, the theory provides a basis to explain ourselves and our world without surrendering to the illusions ofusing necessitarian thought andor predetermined institutional arrangements.<ref name= "fn xvii"/>
 
At the extreme, the theory of ''false necessity'' contributes to the radical project by criticizingcriticizes and thus unifyingunifies strands of the radical tradition. It frees leftist and liberal ideals from institutional fetishism, and emancipates modernist ideals from structural fetishism. The theory further detaches the radical commitment from utopian claims and provides a theoretical basis for real transformative action.<ref>Unger, Roberto Mangabeira, ''Social Theory: Its Situation and its Task, Politics 2'' (New York: Verso, 1987), chapter 7.</ref> That transformative action, Unger believes, does not have to be a complete overhaul or total revolution, but rather is "a piecemeal but cumulative change in the organization of society."<ref>Unger, Robero Mangabeira, ''False necessity: anti-necessitarian social theory in the service of radical democracy: from Politics, a work in constructive social theory'' (London: Verso, 2004), xix.</ref> The keyAccording to theone projectcritic, in the words"key ofto onethe critic,project" "is to "complete the rebellion against the naturalistic fallacy (that is, the confusion of accident with essence and contingency with necessity) and to effect an irrevocable emancipation from false necessity."<ref>Hutchinson, Allan C. “Review: A Poetic Champion Composes: Unger (Not) on Ecology and Women.” The University of Toronto Law Journal 40, no. 2 (April 1, 1990): 275.</ref>
 
==See also==