Jump to content

Measure (mathematics): Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎Additivity: < ∞ is just fine in this context
Finq (talk | contribs)
add better citation to archimedes measurement of the circle.
(32 intermediate revisions by 26 users not shown)
Line 5: Line 5:
[[File:Measure illustration (Vector).svg|alt=|thumb|Informally, a measure has the property of being [[Monotone function|monotone]] in the sense that if <math>A</math> is a [[subset]] of <math>B,</math> the measure of <math>A</math> is less than or equal to the measure of <math>B.</math> Furthermore, the measure of the [[empty set]] is required to be 0. A simple example is a volume (how big an object occupies a space) as a measure.]]
[[File:Measure illustration (Vector).svg|alt=|thumb|Informally, a measure has the property of being [[Monotone function|monotone]] in the sense that if <math>A</math> is a [[subset]] of <math>B,</math> the measure of <math>A</math> is less than or equal to the measure of <math>B.</math> Furthermore, the measure of the [[empty set]] is required to be 0. A simple example is a volume (how big an object occupies a space) as a measure.]]


In [[mathematics]], the concept of a '''measure''' is a generalization and formalization of [[Geometry#Length, area, and volume|geometrical measures]] ([[length]], [[area]], [[volume]]) and other common notions, such as [[magnitude (mathematics)|magnitude]], [[mass]], and [[probability]] of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many similarities and can often be treated together in a single mathematical context. Measures are foundational in [[probability theory]], [[integral|integration theory]], and can be generalized to assume [[signed measure|negative values]], as with [[electrical charge]]. Far-reaching generalizations (such as [[spectral measure]]s and [[projection-valued measure]]s) of measure are widely used in [[quantum physics]] and physics in general.
In [[mathematics]], the concept of a '''measure''' is a generalization and formalization of [[geometrical measures]] ([[length]], [[area]], [[volume]]) and other common notions, such as [[magnitude (mathematics)|magnitude]], [[mass]], and [[probability]] of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many similarities and can often be treated together in a single mathematical context. Measures are foundational in [[probability theory]], [[integral|integration theory]], and can be generalized to assume [[signed measure|negative values]], as with [[electrical charge]]. Far-reaching generalizations (such as [[spectral measure]]s and [[projection-valued measure]]s) of measure are widely used in [[quantum physics]] and physics in general.


The intuition behind this concept dates back to [[ancient Greece]], when [[Archimedes]] tried to calculate the area of a circle. But it was not until the late 19th and early 20th centuries that measure theory became a branch of mathematics. The foundations of modern measure theory were laid in the works of [[Émile Borel]], [[Henri Lebesgue]], [[Nikolai Luzin]], [[Johann Radon]], [[Constantin Carathéodory]], and [[Maurice Fréchet]], among others.
The intuition behind this concept dates back to [[ancient Greece]], when [[Archimedes]] tried to calculate the [[area of a circle]].<ref>Archimedes [https://web.archive.org/web/20040703122928/http://www.math.ubc.ca/~cass/archimedes/circle.html Measuring the Circle]</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Heath |first=T. L. |url=http://archive.org/details/worksofarchimede029517mbp |title=The Works Of Archimedes |date=1897 |publisher=Cambridge University Press. |others=Osmania University, Digital Library Of India |pages=91-98 |chapter=Measurement of a Circle}}</ref> But it was not until the late 19th and early 20th centuries that measure theory became a branch of mathematics. The foundations of modern measure theory were laid in the works of [[Émile Borel]], [[Henri Lebesgue]], [[Nikolai Luzin]], [[Johann Radon]], [[Constantin Carathéodory]], and [[Maurice Fréchet]], among others.


==Definition==
==Definition==
[[File:Countable additivity of a measure.svg|thumb|300px|Countable additivity of a measure <math>\mu</math>: The measure of a countable disjoint union is the same as the sum of all measures of each subset.]]
[[File:Countable additivity of a measure.svg|thumb|300px|Countable additivity of a measure <math>\mu</math>: The measure of a countable disjoint union is the same as the sum of all measures of each subset.]]


Let <math>X</math> be a set and <math>\Sigma</math> a [[Sigma-algebra|<math>\sigma</math>-algebra]] over <math>X.</math> A [[set function]] <math>\mu</math> from <math>\Sigma</math> to the [[extended real number line]] is called a '''measure''' if it satisfies the following properties:
Let <math>X</math> be a set and <math>\Sigma</math> a [[Sigma-algebra|<math>\sigma</math>-algebra]] over <math>X.</math> A [[set function]] <math>\mu</math> from <math>\Sigma</math> to the [[extended real number line]] is called a '''measure''' if the following conditions hold:


*'''Non-negativity''': For all <math>E</math> in <math>\Sigma,</math> we have <math>\mu(E) \geq 0.</math>
*'''Non-negativity''': For all <math>E \in \Sigma, \ \ \mu(E) \geq 0.</math>
*'''Null empty set''': <math>\mu(\varnothing) = 0.</math>
*<math>\mu(\varnothing) = 0.</math>
*'''Countable additivity''' (or [[sigma additivity|<math>\sigma</math>-additivity]]): For all [[countable]] collections <math>\{ E_k \}_{k=1}^\infty</math> of pairwise [[disjoint sets]] in Σ,<math display="block">\mu\left(\bigcup_{k=1}^\infty E_k\right)=\sum_{k=1}^\infty \mu(E_k).</math>
*'''Countable additivity''' (or [[sigma additivity|<math>\sigma</math>-additivity]]): For all [[countable]] collections <math>\{ E_k \}_{k=1}^\infty</math> of pairwise [[disjoint sets]] in Σ,<math display="block">\mu\left(\bigcup_{k=1}^\infty E_k\right)=\sum_{k=1}^\infty \mu(E_k).</math>


Line 35: Line 35:


* The [[counting measure]] is defined by <math>\mu(S)</math> = number of elements in <math>S.</math>
* The [[counting measure]] is defined by <math>\mu(S)</math> = number of elements in <math>S.</math>
* The [[Lebesgue measure]] on <math>\R</math> is a [[Complete measure|complete]] [[translational invariance|translation-invariant]] measure on a ''σ''-algebra containing the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]]s in <math>\R</math> such that <math>\mu([0, 1]) = 1</math>; and every other measure with these properties extends Lebesgue measure.
* The [[Lebesgue measure]] on <math>\R</math> is a [[Complete measure|complete]] [[translational invariance|translation-invariant]] measure on a ''σ''-algebra containing the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]]s in <math>\R</math> such that <math>\mu([0, 1]) = 1</math>; and every other measure with these properties extends the Lebesgue measure.
* Circular [[angle]] measure is invariant under [[rotation]], and [[hyperbolic angle]] measure is invariant under [[squeeze mapping]].
* Circular [[angle]] measure is invariant under [[rotation]], and [[hyperbolic angle]] measure is invariant under [[squeeze mapping]].
* The [[Haar measure]] for a [[Locally compact space|locally compact]] [[topological group]] is a generalization of the Lebesgue measure (and also of counting measure and circular angle measure) and has similar uniqueness properties.
* The [[Haar measure]] for a [[Locally compact space|locally compact]] [[topological group]] is a generalization of the Lebesgue measure (and also of counting measure and circular angle measure) and has similar uniqueness properties.
* The [[Hausdorff measure]] is a generalization of the Lebesgue measure to sets with non-integer dimension, in particular, fractal sets.
* The [[Hausdorff measure]] is a generalization of the Lebesgue measure to sets with non-integer dimension, in particular, fractal sets.
* Every [[probability space]] gives rise to a measure which takes the value 1 on the whole space (and therefore takes all its values in the [[unit interval]] [0, 1]). Such a measure is called a ''probability measure'' or ''distribution''. See the [[List_of_probability_distributions|list of probability distributions]] for instances.
* Every [[probability space]] gives rise to a measure which takes the value 1 on the whole space (and therefore takes all its values in the [[unit interval]] [0, 1]). Such a measure is called a ''probability measure'' or ''distribution''. See the [[list of probability distributions]] for instances.
* The [[Dirac measure]] ''δ''<sub>''a''</sub> (cf. [[Dirac delta function]]) is given by ''δ''<sub>''a''</sub>(''S'') = ''χ''<sub>''S''</sub>(a), where ''χ''<sub>''S''</sub> is the [[indicator function]] of <math>S.</math> The measure of a set is 1 if it contains the point <math>a</math> and 0 otherwise.
* The [[Dirac measure]] ''δ''<sub>''a''</sub> (cf. [[Dirac delta function]]) is given by ''δ''<sub>''a''</sub>(''S'') = ''χ''<sub>''S''</sub>(a), where ''χ''<sub>''S''</sub> is the [[indicator function]] of <math>S.</math> The measure of a set is 1 if it contains the point <math>a</math> and 0 otherwise.


Line 48: Line 48:
* [[Liouville's theorem (Hamiltonian)#Symplectic geometry|Liouville measure]], known also as the natural volume form on a symplectic manifold, is useful in classical statistical and Hamiltonian mechanics.
* [[Liouville's theorem (Hamiltonian)#Symplectic geometry|Liouville measure]], known also as the natural volume form on a symplectic manifold, is useful in classical statistical and Hamiltonian mechanics.
* [[Gibbs measure]] is widely used in statistical mechanics, often under the name [[canonical ensemble]].
* [[Gibbs measure]] is widely used in statistical mechanics, often under the name [[canonical ensemble]].

Measure theory is used in machine learning. One example is the Flow Induced Probability Measure in GFlowNet.<ref>{{cite arXiv | eprint=2111.09266 | last1=Bengio | first1=Yoshua | last2=Lahlou | first2=Salem | last3=Deleu | first3=Tristan | last4=Hu | first4=Edward J. | last5=Tiwari | first5=Mo | last6=Bengio | first6=Emmanuel | title=GFlowNet Foundations | date=2021 | class=cs.LG }}</ref>


==Basic properties==
==Basic properties==
Line 80: Line 82:
A measure can be extended to a complete one by considering the σ-algebra of subsets <math>Y</math> which differ by a negligible set from a measurable set <math>X,</math> that is, such that the [[symmetric difference]] of <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> is contained in a null set. One defines <math>\mu(Y)</math> to equal <math>\mu(X).</math>
A measure can be extended to a complete one by considering the σ-algebra of subsets <math>Y</math> which differ by a negligible set from a measurable set <math>X,</math> that is, such that the [[symmetric difference]] of <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> is contained in a null set. One defines <math>\mu(Y)</math> to equal <math>\mu(X).</math>


==="Dropping the Edge"===
===μ{''x'' : ''f''(''x'') ≥ ''t''} = μ{''x'' : ''f''(''x'') > ''t''} (a.e.)===
If <math>f:X\to[0,+\infty]</math> is <math>(\Sigma,{\cal B}([0,+\infty]))</math>-measurable, then
If <math>f:X\to[0,+\infty]</math> is <math>(\Sigma,{\cal B}([0,+\infty]))</math>-measurable, then
<math display=block>\mu\{x\in X: f(x) \geq t\} = \mu\{x\in X: f(x) > t\}</math>
<math display=block>\mu\{x\in X: f(x) \geq t\} = \mu\{x\in X: f(x) > t\}</math>
for [[almost everywhere|almost all]] <math>t \in X.</math><ref>{{citation | last = Fremlin | first = D. H. | title = Measure Theory | volume = 2 | year = 2010 | edition = Second | page = 221}}</ref> This property is used in connection with [[Lebesgue integral]].
for [[almost everywhere|almost all]] <math>t \in [-\infty,\infty].</math><ref>{{citation | last = Fremlin | first = D. H. | title = Measure Theory | volume = 2 | year = 2010 | edition = Second | page = 221}}</ref> This property is used in connection with [[Lebesgue integral]].
{{math proof| proof=
{{math proof| proof=
Both <math>F(t) := \mu\{x\in X : f(x) > t\}</math> and <math>G(t) := \mu\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\}</math> are monotonically non-increasing functions of <math>t,</math> so both of them have [[Discontinuities of monotone functions|at most countably many discontinuities]] and thus they are continuous almost everywhere, relative to the Lebesgue measure.
Both <math>F(t) := \mu\{x\in X : f(x) > t\}</math> and <math>G(t) := \mu\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\}</math> are monotonically non-increasing functions of <math>t,</math> so both of them have [[Discontinuities of monotone functions|at most countably many discontinuities]] and thus they are continuous almost everywhere, relative to the Lebesgue measure.
Line 94: Line 96:
Arguing as above, <math>\mu\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\} = +\infty </math> when <math>t < t_0.</math> Similarly, if <math>t_0 \geq 0</math> and <math>F\left(t_0\right) = +\infty</math> then <math>F\left(t_0\right) = G\left(t_0\right).</math>
Arguing as above, <math>\mu\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\} = +\infty </math> when <math>t < t_0.</math> Similarly, if <math>t_0 \geq 0</math> and <math>F\left(t_0\right) = +\infty</math> then <math>F\left(t_0\right) = G\left(t_0\right).</math>


For <math>t > t_0,</math> let <math>t_n</math> be a monotonically non-decreasing sequence converging to <math>t.</math> The monotonically non-increasing sequence <math>\{x\in X : f(x) > t_n\}</math> of members of <math>\Sigma</math> has at least one finitely <math>\mu</math>-measurable component, and
For <math>t > t_0,</math> let <math>t_n</math> be a monotonically non-decreasing sequence converging to <math>t.</math> The monotonically non-increasing sequences <math>\{x\in X : f(x) > t_n\}</math> of members of <math>\Sigma</math> has at least one finitely <math>\mu</math>-measurable component, and
<math display=block>\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\} = \bigcap_n \{x\in X : f(x) > t_n\}.</math>
<math display=block>\{x\in X : f(x) \geq t\} = \bigcap_n \{x\in X : f(x) > t_n\}.</math>
Continuity from above guarantees that
Continuity from above guarantees that
Line 110: Line 112:
<math display=block>\bigcup_{\alpha\in\lambda} X_\alpha \in \Sigma</math>
<math display=block>\bigcup_{\alpha\in\lambda} X_\alpha \in \Sigma</math>
<math display=block>\mu\left(\bigcup_{\alpha\in\lambda} X_\alpha\right) = \sum_{\alpha\in\lambda}\mu\left(X_\alpha\right).</math>
<math display=block>\mu\left(\bigcup_{\alpha\in\lambda} X_\alpha\right) = \sum_{\alpha\in\lambda}\mu\left(X_\alpha\right).</math>
Note that the second condition is equivalent to the statement that the [[Ideal (set theory)|ideal]] of null sets is <math>\kappa</math>-complete.
The second condition is equivalent to the statement that the [[Ideal (set theory)|ideal]] of null sets is <math>\kappa</math>-complete.


===Sigma-finite measures===
===Sigma-finite measures===
Line 123: Line 125:


===Semifinite measures===
===Semifinite measures===
Let <math>X</math> be a set, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a sigma-algebra on <math>X,</math> and let <math>\mu</math> be a measure on <math>{\cal A}.</math> We say <math>\mu</math> is '''semifinite''' to mean that for all <math>A\in\mu^\text{pre}\{+\infty\},</math> <math>{\cal P}(A)\cap\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{>0})\ne\emptyset.</math>{{sfn|Mukherjea|1985|p=90}}
Let <math>X</math> be a set, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a sigma-algebra on <math>X,</math> and let <math>\mu</math> be a measure on <math>{\cal A}.</math> We say <math>\mu</math> is '''semifinite''' to mean that for all <math>A\in\mu^\text{pre}\{+\infty\},</math> <math>{\cal P}(A)\cap\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{>0})\ne\emptyset.</math>{{sfn|Mukherjea|Pothoven|1985|p=90}}


Semifinite measures generalize sigma-finite measures, in such a way that some big theorems of measure theory that hold for sigma-finite but not arbitrary measures can be extended with little modification to hold for semifinite measures. (To-do: add examples of such theorems; cf. the talk page.)
Semifinite measures generalize sigma-finite measures, in such a way that some big theorems of measure theory that hold for sigma-finite but not arbitrary measures can be extended with little modification to hold for semifinite measures. (To-do: add examples of such theorems; cf. the talk page.)
Line 145: Line 147:
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=(\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\cap\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{\ge0})\})_{A\in{\cal A}}.</math>{{sfn|Nielsen|1997|loc=Exercise 11.30, p. 159}}
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=(\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\cap\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{\ge0})\})_{A\in{\cal A}}.</math>{{sfn|Nielsen|1997|loc=Exercise 11.30, p. 159}}
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=(\sup\{\mu(A\cap B):B\in\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{\ge0})\})_{A\in{\cal A}}\}.</math>{{sfn|Fremlin|2016|loc=Section 213X, part (c)}}
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=(\sup\{\mu(A\cap B):B\in\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{\ge0})\})_{A\in{\cal A}}\}.</math>{{sfn|Fremlin|2016|loc=Section 213X, part (c)}}
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=\mu|_{\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{>0})}\cup\{A\in{\cal A}:\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\}=+\infty\}\times\{+\infty\}\cup\{A\in{\cal A}:\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\}<+\infty\}\times\{0\}.</math>{{sfn|Royden|2010|loc=Exercise 17.8, p. 342}}
* <math>\mu_\text{sf}=\mu|_{\mu^\text{pre}(\R_{>0})}\cup\{A\in{\cal A}:\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\}=+\infty\}\times\{+\infty\}\cup\{A\in{\cal A}:\sup\{\mu(B):B\in{\cal P}(A)\}<+\infty\}\times\{0\}.</math>{{sfn|Royden|Fitzpatrick|2010|loc=Exercise 17.8, p. 342}}


Since <math>\mu_\text{sf}</math> is semifinite, it follows that if <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}</math> then <math>\mu</math> is semifinite. It is also evident that if <math>\mu</math> is semifinite then <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}.</math>
Since <math>\mu_\text{sf}</math> is semifinite, it follows that if <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}</math> then <math>\mu</math> is semifinite. It is also evident that if <math>\mu</math> is semifinite then <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}.</math>
Line 152: Line 154:
Every ''<math>0-\infty</math> measure'' that is not the zero measure is not semifinite. (Here, we say ''<math>0-\infty</math> measure'' to mean a measure whose range lies in <math>\{0,+\infty\}</math>: <math>(\forall A\in{\cal A})(\mu(A)\in\{0,+\infty\}).</math>) Below we give examples of <math>0-\infty</math> measures that are not zero measures.
Every ''<math>0-\infty</math> measure'' that is not the zero measure is not semifinite. (Here, we say ''<math>0-\infty</math> measure'' to mean a measure whose range lies in <math>\{0,+\infty\}</math>: <math>(\forall A\in{\cal A})(\mu(A)\in\{0,+\infty\}).</math>) Below we give examples of <math>0-\infty</math> measures that are not zero measures.
* Let <math>X</math> be nonempty, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a <math>\sigma</math>-algebra on <math>X,</math> let <math>f:X\to\{0,+\infty\}</math> be not the zero function, and let <math>\mu=(\sum_{x\in A}f(x))_{A\in{\cal A}}.</math> It can be shown that <math>\mu</math> is a measure.
* Let <math>X</math> be nonempty, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a <math>\sigma</math>-algebra on <math>X,</math> let <math>f:X\to\{0,+\infty\}</math> be not the zero function, and let <math>\mu=(\sum_{x\in A}f(x))_{A\in{\cal A}}.</math> It can be shown that <math>\mu</math> is a measure.
** <math>\mu=\{(\emptyset,0)\}\cup({\cal A}\setminus\{\emptyset\})\times\{+\infty\}.</math>{{sfn|Hewitt|1965|loc=part (b) of Example 10.4, p. 127}}
** <math>\mu=\{(\emptyset,0)\}\cup({\cal A}\setminus\{\emptyset\})\times\{+\infty\}.</math>{{sfn|Hewitt|Stromberg|1965|loc=part (b) of Example 10.4, p. 127}}
*** <math>X=\{0\},</math> <math>{\cal A}=\{\emptyset,X\},</math> <math>\mu=\{(\emptyset,0),(X,+\infty)\}.</math>{{sfn|Fremlin|2016|loc=Section 211O, p. 15}}
*** <math>X=\{0\},</math> <math>{\cal A}=\{\emptyset,X\},</math> <math>\mu=\{(\emptyset,0),(X,+\infty)\}.</math>{{sfn|Fremlin|2016|loc=Section 211O, p. 15}}
* Let <math>X</math> be uncountable, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a <math>\sigma</math>-algebra on <math>X,</math> let <math>{\cal C}=\{A\in{\cal A}:A\text{ is countable}\}</math> be the countable elements of <math>{\cal A},</math> and let <math>\mu={\cal C}\times\{0\}\cup({\cal A}\setminus{\cal C})\times\{+\infty\}.</math> It can be shown that <math>\mu</math> is a measure.{{sfn|Mukherjea|1985|p=90}}
* Let <math>X</math> be uncountable, let <math>{\cal A}</math> be a <math>\sigma</math>-algebra on <math>X,</math> let <math>{\cal C}=\{A\in{\cal A}:A\text{ is countable}\}</math> be the countable elements of <math>{\cal A},</math> and let <math>\mu={\cal C}\times\{0\}\cup({\cal A}\setminus{\cal C})\times\{+\infty\}.</math> It can be shown that <math>\mu</math> is a measure.{{sfn|Mukherjea|Pothoven|1985|p=90}}


====Involved non-example====
====Involved non-example====
Line 162: Line 164:
|source=''Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis'' (1985)
|source=''Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis'' (1985)
}}
}}
{{Math theorem|name=Theorem (Luther decomposition){{sfn|Luther|1967|loc=Theorem 1}}{{sfn|Mukherjea|1985|loc=part (b) of Proposition 2.3, p. 90}}|math_statement=
{{Math theorem|name=Theorem (Luther decomposition){{sfn|Luther|1967|loc=Theorem 1}}{{sfn|Mukherjea|Pothoven|1985|loc=part (b) of Proposition 2.3, p. 90}}|math_statement=
For any measure <math>\mu</math> on <math>{\cal A},</math> there exists a <math>0-\infty</math> measure <math>\xi</math> on <math>{\cal A}</math> such that <math>\mu=\nu+\xi</math> for some semifinite measure <math>\nu</math> on <math>{\cal A}.</math> In fact, among such measures <math>\xi,</math> there exists a [[Greatest element and least element|least]] measure <math>\mu_{0-\infty}.</math> Also, we have <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}+\mu_{0-\infty}.</math>
For any measure <math>\mu</math> on <math>{\cal A},</math> there exists a <math>0-\infty</math> measure <math>\xi</math> on <math>{\cal A}</math> such that <math>\mu=\nu+\xi</math> for some semifinite measure <math>\nu</math> on <math>{\cal A}.</math> In fact, among such measures <math>\xi,</math> there exists a [[Greatest element and least element|least]] measure <math>\mu_{0-\infty}.</math> Also, we have <math>\mu=\mu_\text{sf}+\mu_{0-\infty}.</math>
}}
}}
Line 182: Line 184:
{{Main|s-finite measure}}
{{Main|s-finite measure}}


A measure is said to be s-finite if it is a countable sum of bounded measures. S-finite measures are more general than sigma-finite ones and have applications in the theory of [[stochastic processes]].
A measure is said to be s-finite if it is a countable sum of finite measures. S-finite measures are more general than sigma-finite ones and have applications in the theory of [[stochastic processes]].


==Non-measurable sets==
==Non-measurable sets==
Line 241: Line 243:
{{refbegin}}
{{refbegin}}
* [[Robert G. Bartle]] (1995) ''The Elements of Integration and Lebesgue Measure'', Wiley Interscience.
* [[Robert G. Bartle]] (1995) ''The Elements of Integration and Lebesgue Measure'', Wiley Interscience.
* {{citation | last=Bauer|first=H.|title=Measure and Integration Theory|year=2001|publisher=de Gruyter|location=Berlin|isbn=978-3110167191}}
* {{citation | last=Bauer|first=Heinz|authorlink=Heinz Bauer|title=Measure and Integration Theory|year=2001|publisher=de Gruyter|location=Berlin|isbn=978-3110167191}}
* {{citation | last=Bear|first=H.S.|title=A Primer of Lebesgue Integration|year=2001|publisher=Academic Press|location=San Diego|isbn=978-0120839711}}
* {{citation | last=Bear|first=H.S.|title=A Primer of Lebesgue Integration|year=2001|publisher=Academic Press|location=San Diego|isbn=978-0120839711}}
* {{cite book |last1=Berberian |first1=Sterling K |title=Measure and Integration |date=1965 |publisher=MacMillan}}
* {{cite book |last1=Berberian |first1=Sterling K |title=Measure and Integration |date=1965 |publisher=MacMillan}}
* {{citation | last=Bogachev|first=V. I.|title=Measure theory|year=2006|publisher=Springer|location=Berlin|isbn=978-3540345138}}
* {{citation | last=Bogachev|first=Vladimir I.|authorlink=Vladimir Bogachev|title=Measure theory|year=2006|publisher=Springer|location=Berlin|isbn=978-3540345138}}
* {{citation | last=Bourbaki| first=Nicolas | title=Integration I | year=2004 | publisher=[[Springer Verlag]] | isbn=3-540-41129-1}} Chapter III.
* {{citation | last=Bourbaki| first=Nicolas | title=Integration I | year=2004 | publisher=[[Springer Verlag]] | isbn=3-540-41129-1}} Chapter III.
* R. M. Dudley, 2002. ''Real Analysis and Probability''. Cambridge University Press.
* {{cite book |last=Dudley|first=Richard M.|authorlink=Richard M. Dudley| title=Real Analysis and Probability | year=2002 |publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-0521007542}}
* {{cite book |last1=Edgar |first1=Gerald A |title=Integral, Probability, and Fractal Measures |date=1998 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4419-3112-2}}
* {{cite book |last1=Edgar |first1=Gerald A. |title=Integral, Probability, and Fractal Measures |date=1998 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4419-3112-2}}
* {{cite book |last1=Folland |first1=Gerald B |title=Real Analysis: Modern Techniques and Their Applications |date=1999 |publisher=Wiley |isbn=0-471-31716-0 |edition=Second}}
* {{cite book |last1=Folland |first1=Gerald B. |authorlink=Gerald Folland|title=Real Analysis: Modern Techniques and Their Applications |date=1999 |publisher=Wiley |isbn=0-471-31716-0 |edition=Second}}
* Federer, Herbert. Geometric measure theory. Die Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften, Band 153 Springer-Verlag New York Inc., New York 1969 xiv+676 pp.
* Federer, Herbert. Geometric measure theory. Die Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften, Band 153 Springer-Verlag New York Inc., New York 1969 xiv+676 pp.
* {{cite book |last1=Fremlin |first1=D.H. |title=Measure Theory, Volume 2: Broad Foundations |date=2016 |publisher=Torres Fremlin |edition=Hardback}} Second printing.
* {{cite book |last1=Fremlin |first1=D.H. |title=Measure Theory, Volume 2: Broad Foundations |date=2016 |publisher=Torres Fremlin |edition=Hardback}} Second printing.
* {{cite book |last1=Hewitt |first1=Edward |last2=Stromberg |first2=Karl |title=Real and Abstract Analysis: A Modern Treatment of the Theory of Functions of a Real Variable |date=1965 |publisher=Springer |isbn=0-387-90138-8}}
* {{cite book |last1=Hewitt |first1=Edward |last2=Stromberg |first2=Karl |title=Real and Abstract Analysis: A Modern Treatment of the Theory of Functions of a Real Variable |date=1965 |publisher=Springer |isbn=0-387-90138-8}}
* {{citation | last=Jech| first=Thomas | title=Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded | year=2003 | publisher=[[Springer Verlag]] | isbn=3-540-44085-2}}
* {{citation | last=Jech| first=Thomas | title=Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded | year=2003 | publisher=[[Springer Verlag]] | isbn=3-540-44085-2}}
* [[R. Duncan Luce]] and Louis Narens (1987). "measurement, theory of," ''The [[New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics]]'', v. 3, pp. 428–32.
* [[R. Duncan Luce]] and Louis Narens (1987). "measurement, theory of", ''The [[New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics]]'', v. 3, pp. 428–32.
* {{cite journal |last1=Luther |first1=Norman Y |title=A decomposition of measures |journal=Canadian Journal of Mathematics |date=1967 |volume=20 |pages=953–959 |doi=10.4153/CJM-1968-092-0 |s2cid=124262782 |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/canadian-journal-of-mathematics/article/decomposition-of-measures/B4356A177FCF019EA9B0A3C8AC40BB6B}}
* {{cite journal |last1=Luther |first1=Norman Y |title=A decomposition of measures |journal=Canadian Journal of Mathematics |date=1967 |volume=20 |pages=953–959 |doi=10.4153/CJM-1968-092-0 |s2cid=124262782 |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/canadian-journal-of-mathematics/article/decomposition-of-measures/B4356A177FCF019EA9B0A3C8AC40BB6B|doi-access=free }}
* {{cite book |last1=Mukherjea |first1=A |last2=Pothoven |first2=K |title=Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis |date=1985 |publisher=Plenum Press |edition=Second |url=https://link.springer.com/book/9781441974587}}
* {{cite book |last1=Mukherjea |first1=A |last2=Pothoven |first2=K |title=Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis |date=1985 |publisher=Plenum Press |edition=Second |url=https://link.springer.com/book/9781441974587}}
** The first edition was published with ''Part B: Functional Analysis'' as a single volume: {{cite book |last1=Mukherjea |first1=A |last2=Pothoven |first2=K |title=Real and Functional Analysis |date=1978 |publisher=Plenum Press |doi=10.1007/978-1-4684-2331-0 |isbn=978-1-4684-2333-4 |edition=First |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-1-4684-2331-0}}
** The first edition was published with ''Part B: Functional Analysis'' as a single volume: {{cite book |last1=Mukherjea |first1=A |last2=Pothoven |first2=K |title=Real and Functional Analysis |date=1978 |publisher=Plenum Press |doi=10.1007/978-1-4684-2331-0 |isbn=978-1-4684-2333-4 |edition=First |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-1-4684-2331-0}}
Line 260: Line 262:
* {{cite book |last1=Nielsen |first1=Ole A |title=An Introduction to Integration and Measure Theory |date=1997 |publisher=Wiley |isbn=0-471-59518-7}}
* {{cite book |last1=Nielsen |first1=Ole A |title=An Introduction to Integration and Measure Theory |date=1997 |publisher=Wiley |isbn=0-471-59518-7}}
* {{Citation|author=K. P. S. Bhaskara Rao and M. Bhaskara Rao|title=Theory of Charges: A Study of Finitely Additive Measures| publisher=Academic Press|location=London|year=1983|pages=x + 315|isbn=0-12-095780-9}}
* {{Citation|author=K. P. S. Bhaskara Rao and M. Bhaskara Rao|title=Theory of Charges: A Study of Finitely Additive Measures| publisher=Academic Press|location=London|year=1983|pages=x + 315|isbn=0-12-095780-9}}
* {{cite book |last1=Royden |first1=H.L. |last2=Fitzpatrick |first2=P.M. |author1-link=Halsey Royden |title=Real Analysis |date=2010 |publisher=Prentice Hall |page=342, Exercise 17.8 |edition=Fourth}} First printing. Note that there is a later (2017) second printing. Though usually there is little difference between the first and subsequent printings, in this case the second printing not only deletes from page 53 the Exercises 36, 40, 41, and 42 of Chapter 2 but also offers a (slightly, but still substantially) different presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8. (The second printing's presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8 (on the Luther{{sfn|Luther|1967|loc=Theorem 1}} decomposition) agrees with usual presentations,{{sfn|Mukherjea|1985|p=90}}{{sfn|Folland|1999|p=27|loc=Exercise 1.15.a}} whereas the first printing's presentation provides a fresh perspective.)
* {{cite book |last1=Royden |first1=H.L. |last2=Fitzpatrick |first2=P.M. |author1-link=Halsey Royden |title=Real Analysis |date=2010 |publisher=Prentice Hall |page=342, Exercise 17.8 |edition=Fourth}} First printing. There is a later (2017) second printing. Though usually there is little difference between the first and subsequent printings, in this case the second printing not only deletes from page 53 the Exercises 36, 40, 41, and 42 of Chapter 2 but also offers a (slightly, but still substantially) different presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8. (The second printing's presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8 (on the Luther{{sfn|Luther|1967|loc=Theorem 1}} decomposition) agrees with usual presentations,{{sfn|Mukherjea|Pothoven|1985|p=90}}{{sfn|Folland|1999|p=27|loc=Exercise 1.15.a}} whereas the first printing's presentation provides a fresh perspective.)
* Shilov, G. E., and Gurevich, B. L., 1978. ''Integral, Measure, and Derivative: A Unified Approach'', Richard A. Silverman, trans. Dover Publications. {{isbn|0-486-63519-8}}. Emphasizes the [[Daniell integral]].
* Shilov, G. E., and Gurevich, B. L., 1978. ''Integral, Measure, and Derivative: A Unified Approach'', Richard A. Silverman, trans. Dover Publications. {{isbn|0-486-63519-8}}. Emphasizes the [[Daniell integral]].
* {{citation | last = Teschl| first = Gerald| author-link = Gerald Teschl| title = Topics in Real and Functional Analysis| url = https://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~gerald/ftp/book-fa/index.html|publisher = (lecture notes)}}
* {{citation | last = Teschl| first = Gerald| author-link = Gerald Teschl| title = Topics in Real and Functional Analysis| url = https://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~gerald/ftp/book-fa/index.html|publisher = (lecture notes)}}

Revision as of 15:43, 13 July 2024

Informally, a measure has the property of being monotone in the sense that if is a subset of the measure of is less than or equal to the measure of Furthermore, the measure of the empty set is required to be 0. A simple example is a volume (how big an object occupies a space) as a measure.

In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures (length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as magnitude, mass, and probability of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many similarities and can often be treated together in a single mathematical context. Measures are foundational in probability theory, integration theory, and can be generalized to assume negative values, as with electrical charge. Far-reaching generalizations (such as spectral measures and projection-valued measures) of measure are widely used in quantum physics and physics in general.

The intuition behind this concept dates back to ancient Greece, when Archimedes tried to calculate the area of a circle.[1][2] But it was not until the late 19th and early 20th centuries that measure theory became a branch of mathematics. The foundations of modern measure theory were laid in the works of Émile Borel, Henri Lebesgue, Nikolai Luzin, Johann Radon, Constantin Carathéodory, and Maurice Fréchet, among others.

Definition

Countable additivity of a measure : The measure of a countable disjoint union is the same as the sum of all measures of each subset.

Let be a set and a -algebra over A set function from to the extended real number line is called a measure if the following conditions hold:

  • Non-negativity: For all
  • Countable additivity (or -additivity): For all countable collections of pairwise disjoint sets in Σ,

If at least one set has finite measure, then the requirement is met automatically due to countable additivity: and therefore

If the condition of non-negativity is dropped, and takes on at most one of the values of then is called a signed measure.

The pair is called a measurable space, and the members of are called measurable sets.

A triple is called a measure space. A probability measure is a measure with total measure one – that is, A probability space is a measure space with a probability measure.

For measure spaces that are also topological spaces various compatibility conditions can be placed for the measure and the topology. Most measures met in practice in analysis (and in many cases also in probability theory) are Radon measures. Radon measures have an alternative definition in terms of linear functionals on the locally convex topological vector space of continuous functions with compact support. This approach is taken by Bourbaki (2004) and a number of other sources. For more details, see the article on Radon measures.

Instances

Some important measures are listed here.

Other 'named' measures used in various theories include: Borel measure, Jordan measure, ergodic measure, Gaussian measure, Baire measure, Radon measure, Young measure, and Loeb measure.

In physics an example of a measure is spatial distribution of mass (see for example, gravity potential), or another non-negative extensive property, conserved (see conservation law for a list of these) or not. Negative values lead to signed measures, see "generalizations" below.

  • Liouville measure, known also as the natural volume form on a symplectic manifold, is useful in classical statistical and Hamiltonian mechanics.
  • Gibbs measure is widely used in statistical mechanics, often under the name canonical ensemble.

Measure theory is used in machine learning. One example is the Flow Induced Probability Measure in GFlowNet.[3]

Basic properties

Let be a measure.

Monotonicity

If and are measurable sets with then

Measure of countable unions and intersections

Countable subadditivity

For any countable sequence of (not necessarily disjoint) measurable sets in

Continuity from below

If are measurable sets that are increasing (meaning that ) then the union of the sets is measurable and

Continuity from above

If are measurable sets that are decreasing (meaning that ) then the intersection of the sets is measurable; furthermore, if at least one of the has finite measure then

This property is false without the assumption that at least one of the has finite measure. For instance, for each let which all have infinite Lebesgue measure, but the intersection is empty.

Other properties

Completeness

A measurable set is called a null set if A subset of a null set is called a negligible set. A negligible set need not be measurable, but every measurable negligible set is automatically a null set. A measure is called complete if every negligible set is measurable.

A measure can be extended to a complete one by considering the σ-algebra of subsets which differ by a negligible set from a measurable set that is, such that the symmetric difference of and is contained in a null set. One defines to equal

"Dropping the Edge"

If is -measurable, then for almost all [4] This property is used in connection with Lebesgue integral.

Proof

Both and are monotonically non-increasing functions of so both of them have at most countably many discontinuities and thus they are continuous almost everywhere, relative to the Lebesgue measure. If then so that as desired.

If is such that then monotonicity implies so that as required. If for all then we are done, so assume otherwise. Then there is a unique such that is infinite to the left of (which can only happen when ) and finite to the right. Arguing as above, when Similarly, if and then

For let be a monotonically non-decreasing sequence converging to The monotonically non-increasing sequences of members of has at least one finitely -measurable component, and Continuity from above guarantees that The right-hand side then equals if is a point of continuity of Since is continuous almost everywhere, this completes the proof.

Additivity

Measures are required to be countably additive. However, the condition can be strengthened as follows. For any set and any set of nonnegative define: That is, we define the sum of the to be the supremum of all the sums of finitely many of them.

A measure on is -additive if for any and any family of disjoint sets the following hold: The second condition is equivalent to the statement that the ideal of null sets is -complete.

Sigma-finite measures

A measure space is called finite if is a finite real number (rather than ). Nonzero finite measures are analogous to probability measures in the sense that any finite measure is proportional to the probability measure A measure is called σ-finite if can be decomposed into a countable union of measurable sets of finite measure. Analogously, a set in a measure space is said to have a σ-finite measure if it is a countable union of sets with finite measure.

For example, the real numbers with the standard Lebesgue measure are σ-finite but not finite. Consider the closed intervals for all integers there are countably many such intervals, each has measure 1, and their union is the entire real line. Alternatively, consider the real numbers with the counting measure, which assigns to each finite set of reals the number of points in the set. This measure space is not σ-finite, because every set with finite measure contains only finitely many points, and it would take uncountably many such sets to cover the entire real line. The σ-finite measure spaces have some very convenient properties; σ-finiteness can be compared in this respect to the Lindelöf property of topological spaces.[original research?] They can be also thought of as a vague generalization of the idea that a measure space may have 'uncountable measure'.

Strictly localizable measures

Semifinite measures

Let be a set, let be a sigma-algebra on and let be a measure on We say is semifinite to mean that for all [5]

Semifinite measures generalize sigma-finite measures, in such a way that some big theorems of measure theory that hold for sigma-finite but not arbitrary measures can be extended with little modification to hold for semifinite measures. (To-do: add examples of such theorems; cf. the talk page.)

Basic examples

  • Every sigma-finite measure is semifinite.
  • Assume let and assume for all
    • We have that is sigma-finite if and only if for all and is countable. We have that is semifinite if and only if for all [6]
    • Taking above (so that is counting measure on ), we see that counting measure on is
      • sigma-finite if and only if is countable; and
      • semifinite (without regard to whether is countable). (Thus, counting measure, on the power set of an arbitrary uncountable set gives an example of a semifinite measure that is not sigma-finite.)
  • Let be a complete, separable metric on let be the Borel sigma-algebra induced by and let Then the Hausdorff measure is semifinite.[7]
  • Let be a complete, separable metric on let be the Borel sigma-algebra induced by and let Then the packing measure is semifinite.[8]

Involved example

The zero measure is sigma-finite and thus semifinite. In addition, the zero measure is clearly less than or equal to It can be shown there is a greatest measure with these two properties:

Theorem (semifinite part)[9] — For any measure on there exists, among semifinite measures on that are less than or equal to a greatest element

We say the semifinite part of to mean the semifinite measure defined in the above theorem. We give some nice, explicit formulas, which some authors may take as definition, for the semifinite part:

  • [9]
  • [10]
  • [11]

Since is semifinite, it follows that if then is semifinite. It is also evident that if is semifinite then

Non-examples

Every measure that is not the zero measure is not semifinite. (Here, we say measure to mean a measure whose range lies in : ) Below we give examples of measures that are not zero measures.

  • Let be nonempty, let be a -algebra on let be not the zero function, and let It can be shown that is a measure.
    • [12]
      • [13]
  • Let be uncountable, let be a -algebra on let be the countable elements of and let It can be shown that is a measure.[5]

Involved non-example

Measures that are not semifinite are very wild when restricted to certain sets.[Note 1] Every measure is, in a sense, semifinite once its part (the wild part) is taken away.

— A. Mukherjea and K. Pothoven, Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis (1985)

Theorem (Luther decomposition)[14][15] — For any measure on there exists a measure on such that for some semifinite measure on In fact, among such measures there exists a least measure Also, we have

We say the part of to mean the measure defined in the above theorem. Here is an explicit formula for :

Results regarding semifinite measures

  • Let be oder and let Then is semifinite if and only if is injective.[16][17] (This result has import in the study of the dual space of .)
  • Let be oder and let be the topology of convergence in measure on Then is semifinite if and only if is Hausdorff.[18][19]
  • (Johnson) Let be a set, let be a sigma-algebra on let be a measure on let be a set, let be a sigma-algebra on and let be a measure on If are both not a measure, then both and are semifinite if and only if for all and (Here, is the measure defined in Theorem 39.1 in Berberian '65.[20])

Localizable measures

Localizable measures are a special case of semifinite measures and a generalization of sigma-finite measures.

Let be a set, let be a sigma-algebra on and let be a measure on

  • Let be oder and let Then is localizable if and only if is bijective (if and only if "is" ).[21][17]

s-finite measures

A measure is said to be s-finite if it is a countable sum of finite measures. S-finite measures are more general than sigma-finite ones and have applications in the theory of stochastic processes.

Non-measurable sets

If the axiom of choice is assumed to be true, it can be proved that not all subsets of Euclidean space are Lebesgue measurable; examples of such sets include the Vitali set, and the non-measurable sets postulated by the Hausdorff paradox and the Banach–Tarski paradox.

Generalizations

For certain purposes, it is useful to have a "measure" whose values are not restricted to the non-negative reals or infinity. For instance, a countably additive set function with values in the (signed) real numbers is called a signed measure, while such a function with values in the complex numbers is called a complex measure. Observe, however, that complex measure is necessarily of finite variation, hence complex measures include finite signed measures but not, for example, the Lebesgue measure.

Measures that take values in Banach spaces have been studied extensively.[22] A measure that takes values in the set of self-adjoint projections on a Hilbert space is called a projection-valued measure; these are used in functional analysis for the spectral theorem. When it is necessary to distinguish the usual measures which take non-negative values from generalizations, the term positive measure is used. Positive measures are closed under conical combination but not general linear combination, while signed measures are the linear closure of positive measures.

Another generalization is the finitely additive measure, also known as a content. This is the same as a measure except that instead of requiring countable additivity we require only finite additivity. Historically, this definition was used first. It turns out that in general, finitely additive measures are connected with notions such as Banach limits, the dual of and the Stone–Čech compactification. All these are linked in one way or another to the axiom of choice. Contents remain useful in certain technical problems in geometric measure theory; this is the theory of Banach measures.

A charge is a generalization in both directions: it is a finitely additive, signed measure.[23] (Cf. ba space for information about bounded charges, where we say a charge is bounded to mean its range its a bounded subset of R.)

See also

Notes

  1. ^ One way to rephrase our definition is that is semifinite if and only if Negating this rephrasing, we find that is not semifinite if and only if For every such set the subspace measure induced by the subspace sigma-algebra induced by i.e. the restriction of to said subspace sigma-algebra, is a measure that is not the zero measure.

Bibliography

  • Robert G. Bartle (1995) The Elements of Integration and Lebesgue Measure, Wiley Interscience.
  • Bauer, Heinz (2001), Measure and Integration Theory, Berlin: de Gruyter, ISBN 978-3110167191
  • Bear, H.S. (2001), A Primer of Lebesgue Integration, San Diego: Academic Press, ISBN 978-0120839711
  • Berberian, Sterling K (1965). Measure and Integration. MacMillan.
  • Bogachev, Vladimir I. (2006), Measure theory, Berlin: Springer, ISBN 978-3540345138
  • Bourbaki, Nicolas (2004), Integration I, Springer Verlag, ISBN 3-540-41129-1 Chapter III.
  • Dudley, Richard M. (2002). Real Analysis and Probability. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521007542.
  • Edgar, Gerald A. (1998). Integral, Probability, and Fractal Measures. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4419-3112-2.
  • Folland, Gerald B. (1999). Real Analysis: Modern Techniques and Their Applications (Second ed.). Wiley. ISBN 0-471-31716-0.
  • Federer, Herbert. Geometric measure theory. Die Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften, Band 153 Springer-Verlag New York Inc., New York 1969 xiv+676 pp.
  • Fremlin, D.H. (2016). Measure Theory, Volume 2: Broad Foundations (Hardback ed.). Torres Fremlin. Second printing.
  • Hewitt, Edward; Stromberg, Karl (1965). Real and Abstract Analysis: A Modern Treatment of the Theory of Functions of a Real Variable. Springer. ISBN 0-387-90138-8.
  • Jech, Thomas (2003), Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded, Springer Verlag, ISBN 3-540-44085-2
  • R. Duncan Luce and Louis Narens (1987). "measurement, theory of", The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, v. 3, pp. 428–32.
  • Luther, Norman Y (1967). "A decomposition of measures". Canadian Journal of Mathematics. 20: 953–959. doi:10.4153/CJM-1968-092-0. S2CID 124262782.
  • Mukherjea, A; Pothoven, K (1985). Real and Functional Analysis, Part A: Real Analysis (Second ed.). Plenum Press.
  • M. E. Munroe, 1953. Introduction to Measure and Integration. Addison Wesley.
  • Nielsen, Ole A (1997). An Introduction to Integration and Measure Theory. Wiley. ISBN 0-471-59518-7.
  • K. P. S. Bhaskara Rao and M. Bhaskara Rao (1983), Theory of Charges: A Study of Finitely Additive Measures, London: Academic Press, pp. x + 315, ISBN 0-12-095780-9
  • Royden, H.L.; Fitzpatrick, P.M. (2010). Real Analysis (Fourth ed.). Prentice Hall. p. 342, Exercise 17.8. First printing. There is a later (2017) second printing. Though usually there is little difference between the first and subsequent printings, in this case the second printing not only deletes from page 53 the Exercises 36, 40, 41, and 42 of Chapter 2 but also offers a (slightly, but still substantially) different presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8. (The second printing's presentation of part (ii) of Exercise 17.8 (on the Luther[14] decomposition) agrees with usual presentations,[5][24] whereas the first printing's presentation provides a fresh perspective.)
  • Shilov, G. E., and Gurevich, B. L., 1978. Integral, Measure, and Derivative: A Unified Approach, Richard A. Silverman, trans. Dover Publications. ISBN 0-486-63519-8. Emphasizes the Daniell integral.
  • Teschl, Gerald, Topics in Real and Functional Analysis, (lecture notes)
  • Tao, Terence (2011). An Introduction to Measure Theory. Providence, R.I.: American Mathematical Society. ISBN 9780821869192.
  • Weaver, Nik (2013). Measure Theory and Functional Analysis. World Scientific. ISBN 9789814508568.

References

  1. ^ Archimedes Measuring the Circle
  2. ^ Heath, T. L. (1897). "Measurement of a Circle". The Works Of Archimedes. Osmania University, Digital Library Of India. Cambridge University Press. pp. 91–98.
  3. ^ Bengio, Yoshua; Lahlou, Salem; Deleu, Tristan; Hu, Edward J.; Tiwari, Mo; Bengio, Emmanuel (2021). "GFlowNet Foundations". arXiv:2111.09266 [cs.LG].
  4. ^ Fremlin, D. H. (2010), Measure Theory, vol. 2 (Second ed.), p. 221
  5. ^ a b c Mukherjea & Pothoven 1985, p. 90.
  6. ^ Folland 1999, p. 25.
  7. ^ Edgar 1998, Theorem 1.5.2, p. 42.
  8. ^ Edgar 1998, Theorem 1.5.3, p. 42.
  9. ^ a b Nielsen 1997, Exercise 11.30, p. 159.
  10. ^ Fremlin 2016, Section 213X, part (c).
  11. ^ Royden & Fitzpatrick 2010, Exercise 17.8, p. 342.
  12. ^ Hewitt & Stromberg 1965, part (b) of Example 10.4, p. 127.
  13. ^ Fremlin 2016, Section 211O, p. 15.
  14. ^ a b Luther 1967, Theorem 1.
  15. ^ Mukherjea & Pothoven 1985, part (b) of Proposition 2.3, p. 90.
  16. ^ Fremlin 2016, part (a) of Theorem 243G, p. 159.
  17. ^ a b Fremlin 2016, Section 243K, p. 162.
  18. ^ Fremlin 2016, part (a) of the Theorem in Section 245E, p. 182.
  19. ^ Fremlin 2016, Section 245M, p. 188.
  20. ^ Berberian 1965, Theorem 39.1, p. 129.
  21. ^ Fremlin 2016, part (b) of Theorem 243G, p. 159.
  22. ^ Rao, M. M. (2012), Random and Vector Measures, Series on Multivariate Analysis, vol. 9, World Scientific, ISBN 978-981-4350-81-5, MR 2840012.
  23. ^ Bhaskara Rao, K. P. S. (1983). Theory of charges: a study of finitely additive measures. M. Bhaskara Rao. London: Academic Press. p. 35. ISBN 0-12-095780-9. OCLC 21196971.
  24. ^ Folland 1999, p. 27, Exercise 1.15.a.