Jump to content

Psychological barriers to effective altruism: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎Status: removed sentence: I looked at the cited source, and the claim here seemed to be too sweeping based on the studies reported in the cited source—which makes me wonder about some of the other claims made here
some changes to get the rewrite rolling: start by defining "effective" (this key concept was not clearly before with reference to EA); don't call EA normative, as that is controversial: MacAskill insists that EA is not a normative theory or claim, though Singer would probably disagree; removed red link & #See also links that are in article body, per WP:NOTSEEALSO
Line 1: Line 1:
{{short description|Practice of ineffective giving}}
{{short description|Practice of ineffective giving}}
{{About||the philosophical and ethical movement|Effective altruism|the ethical doctrine|Altruism (ethics)}}
{{Multiple issues |
{{Multiple issues |
{{Cleanup rewrite |date=December 2023}}
{{Cleanup rewrite |date=December 2023}}
Line 7: Line 6:
}}
}}


[[File:Peter Singer no Fronteiras do Pensamento Porto Alegre (9616423447).jpg|thumb|320px|[[Peter Singer]] is one of the prominent philosophers of [[effective altruism]].]]
'''Ineffective altruism''' is the practice of ineffective giving and refers to instances where efforts to do good or contribute to a cause do not produce the intended positive impact.<ref name="Caviola-2021">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Schubert |first2=Stefan |last3=Greene |first3=Joshua D. |date=July 2021 |title=The Psychology of (In)Effective Altruism |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=25 |issue=7 |pages=596–607 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2021.03.015 |pmid=33962844 |issn=1364-6613|doi-access=free }}</ref> It is a concept that has its origins in [[social psychology]],<ref name="Berman-2018" /> [[moral psychology]],<ref name="Greene-2013" /> [[philosophy]]<ref name="Singer-2009" /> and [[Charity (practice)|charitable giving]].<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011">{{Citation |title=Heuristics and Biases in Charity |date=2011-01-19 |work=The Science of Giving |pages=233–254 <!-- |access-date=2023-11-23 --> |publisher=Psychology Press |doi=10.4324/9780203865972-24 |isbn=978-0-203-86597-2}}</ref> In general, humans are motivated to do good things in the world, whether that is through donations to charity, volunteering time for a cause, or just lending a hand to someone who needs help.<ref name="Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)-2023">{{Cite web |author-link=Charities Aid Foundation |date=2023 |title=CAF World Giving Index 2023 |url=https://www.cafonline.org/docs/default-source/about-us-research/wgi_report_2023_final.pdf?sfvrsn=402a5447_2 |access-date=14 November 2023 |website=Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |author-link=Charities Aid Foundation |date=2022 |title=World Giving Index 2022: A global view of giving trends |url=https://www.cafonline.org/docs/default-source/about-us-research/caf_world_giving_index_2022_210922-final.pdf |access-date=10 November 2023 |website=Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)}}</ref> In 2022, approximately 4.2 billion people donated their money, time, or helped a stranger.<ref name="Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)-2023" /> Donating money to charity is especially substantial. For instance, 2% of the [[GDP of the United States]] goes to charitable organizations—a total of more than $450 billion in annual donations.<ref>{{Cite book |title=Giving USA 2020: The Annual Report on Philanthropy for the Year 2019. |publisher=Giving USA Foundation |year=2020 |isbn=9780998746654}}</ref> Despite the human tendency and motivation to give and engage in [[altruistic behavior]], research has shed light on an unequal motivation to give [[Effective altruism|effectively]].<ref name="Caviola-2021" /><ref name="Burum-2020">{{Cite journal |last1=Burum |first1=Bethany |last2=Nowak |first2=Martin A. |last3=Hoffman |first3=Moshe |date=December 2020 |title=An evolutionary explanation for ineffective altruism |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/s41562-020-00950-4 |journal=Nature Human Behaviour |language=en |volume=4 |issue=12 |pages=1245–1257 |doi=10.1038/s41562-020-00950-4 |pmid=33046859 |s2cid=222318993 |issn=2397-3374}}</ref>

In the philosophy of [[effective altruism]], an [[altruistic]] act such as [[Charity (practice)|charitable giving]] is considered more effective, or [[cost-effective]], if it uses a set of resources to do more good per unit of resource than other options, with the goal of trying to do the most good.<ref name="EA-IEE">{{cite encyclopedia |title=Effective altruism |encyclopedia=International Encyclopedia of Ethics |publisher=[[John Wiley & Sons]] |location=Hoboken, New Jersey |url=https://philarchive.org/archive/PUMEA |date=June 2020 |editor-last=LaFollette |editor-first=Hugh |pages=1–9 |doi=10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee883 |isbn=9781444367072 |oclc=829259960 |last2=MacAskill |first2=William |last1=Pummer |first1=Theron |s2cid=241220220}}</ref> Following this definition of effectiveness, researchers in [[psychology]] and related fields have identified '''barriers to effective altruism''' that can cause people to choose less effective options when they engage in altruistic activities such as charitable giving.<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011">{{Citation |title=Heuristics and Biases in Charity |date=2011-01-19 |work=The Science of Giving |pages=233–254 <!-- |access-date=2023-11-23 --> |publisher=Psychology Press |doi=10.4324/9780203865972-24 |isbn=978-0-203-86597-2}}</ref><ref name="Burum-2020">{{Cite journal |last1=Burum |first1=Bethany |last2=Nowak |first2=Martin A. |last3=Hoffman |first3=Moshe |date=December 2020 |title=An evolutionary explanation for ineffective altruism |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/s41562-020-00950-4 |journal=Nature Human Behaviour |language=en |volume=4 |issue=12 |pages=1245–1257 |doi=10.1038/s41562-020-00950-4 |pmid=33046859 |s2cid=222318993 |issn=2397-3374}}</ref><ref name="Caviola-2021">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Schubert |first2=Stefan |last3=Greene |first3=Joshua D. |date=July 2021 |title=The Psychology of (In)Effective Altruism |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=25 |issue=7 |pages=596–607 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2021.03.015 |pmid=33962844 |issn=1364-6613|doi-access=free }}</ref> Such barriers can include the evolutionary predispositions of parochialism, status seeking, and conformity; the motivational obstacles of subjective preferences, a narrow moral circle, and scope neglect; and the epistemic obstacles of overhead aversion, quantifiability skepticism, and ignorance about more effective options.


== Overview ==
== Overview ==
In general, humans are motivated to do good things in the world, whether that is through donations to charity, volunteering time for a cause, or just lending a hand to someone who needs help.<ref name="Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)-2023">{{Cite web |author-link=Charities Aid Foundation |date=2023 |title=CAF World Giving Index 2023 |url=https://www.cafonline.org/docs/default-source/about-us-research/wgi_report_2023_final.pdf?sfvrsn=402a5447_2 |access-date=14 November 2023 |website=Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |author-link=Charities Aid Foundation |date=2022 |title=World Giving Index 2022: A global view of giving trends |url=https://www.cafonline.org/docs/default-source/about-us-research/caf_world_giving_index_2022_210922-final.pdf |access-date=10 November 2023 |website=Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)}}</ref> In 2022, approximately 4.2 billion people donated their money, time, or helped a stranger.<ref name="Charities Aid Foundation (CAF)-2023" /> Donating money to charity is especially substantial. For instance, 2% of the [[GDP of the United States]] goes to charitable organizations—a total of more than $450 billion in annual donations.<ref>{{Cite book |title=Giving USA 2020: The Annual Report on Philanthropy for the Year 2019. |publisher=Giving USA Foundation |year=2020 |isbn=9780998746654}}</ref> Despite the human tendency and motivation to give and engage in [[altruistic behavior]], research has shed light on an unequal motivation to give [[Effective altruism|effectively]].<ref name="Caviola-2021" />
[[File:Peter Singer no Fronteiras do Pensamento Porto Alegre (9616423447).jpg|thumb|320px|[[Peter Singer]] is one of the prominent philosophers behind the [[Normativity|normative framework]] of [[effective altruism]].]]


The term "ineffective altruism" refers to altruistic behavior that leads to a sub-optimal outcome with a given amount of resources.<ref name="Berman-2018" /><ref>{{Cite web |title=What is effective altruism? {{!}} Effective Altruism |url=https://www.effectivealtruism.org/articles/introduction-to-effective-altruism#faq |access-date=2023-11-23 |website=www.effectivealtruism.org |language=en}}</ref> For instance, an altruistic act can be effective if the use of a set of resources saves as many lives as possible.<ref name="Caviola-2021" /><ref name="Lewis-2018">{{Cite journal |last1=Lewis |first1=Joshua |last2=Small |first2=Deborah |date=2018 |editor-last=Gershoff |editor-first=Andrew |editor2-last=Kozinets |editor2-first=Robert |editor3-last=White |editor3-first=Tiffany |title=Ineffective Altruism: Giving Less When Donations Do More |url=https://www.acrwebsite.org/volumes/2412099/volumes/v46/NA-46 |journal=NA - Advances in Consumer Research |location=Duluth, Minnesota |publisher=Association for Consumer Research |volume=46 |pages=194–198}}</ref> The term is unrelated to [[effective altruism]] as a movement, but originates from the ideal of effective altruism as a [[Normativity|normative framework]].{{Citation needed|date=December 2023}}{{Explain|date=December 2023|reason=Who says this? This statement opens a can of worms because there are disagreements within the movement about the role of normativity, and it seems at first glance that not all of the research cited here is indifferent to normative considerations.}}
Humans are motivated to give, but often not motivated to give effectively.<ref name="Burum-2020" /> In the domain of business decisions, investors look for how much return they will get for each dollar they invest. However, when it comes to the domain of altruistic decision-making, this line of thinking is far less common.<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011" /> Most donors seem to prioritize giving to charitable organizations that spend the least possible amount on running costs in the hopes of having more of their donation reach the destination.<ref name="Lewis-2018">{{Cite journal |last1=Lewis |first1=Joshua |last2=Small |first2=Deborah |date=2018 |editor-last=Gershoff |editor-first=Andrew |editor2-last=Kozinets |editor2-first=Robert |editor3-last=White |editor3-first=Tiffany |title=Ineffective Altruism: Giving Less When Donations Do More |url=https://www.acrwebsite.org/volumes/2412099/volumes/v46/NA-46 |journal=NA - Advances in Consumer Research |location=Duluth, Minnesota |publisher=Association for Consumer Research |volume=46 |pages=194–198}}</ref><ref name="Caviola-2014">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Faulmüller |first2=Nadira |last3=Everett |first3=Jim A. C. |last4=Savulescu |first4=Julian |last5=Kahane |first5=Guy |date=July 2014 |title=The evaluability bias in charitable giving: Saving administration costs or saving lives? |url=https://www.proquest.com/docview/1548669952 |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=English |volume=9 |issue=4 |pages=303–315|doi=10.1017/S1930297500006185 |s2cid=18730753 |id={{ProQuest|1548669952}} |doi-access=free }}</ref>


== Evolutionary predispositions ==
=== Paradox of ineffective altruism ===
While plenty of studies in the behavioral sciences have demonstrated the cognitive and emotional limitations in charitable giving, some argue that the reasons behind ineffective giving run deeper.<ref name="Jaeger-2022">{{Cite journal |last1=Jaeger |first1=Bastian |last2=van Vugt |first2=Mark |date=April 2022 |title=Psychological barriers to effective altruism: An evolutionary perspective |journal=Current Opinion in Psychology |volume=44 |pages=130–134 |doi=10.1016/j.copsyc.2021.09.008 |pmid=34628365 |s2cid=238582556 |via=Elsevier Science Direct|doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Burum-2020" /> A study by academics at [[Harvard University]] and the [[Massachusetts Institute of Technology]] suggested that the human tendency to be altruistically ineffective can be explained through [[Evolutionary psychology|evolutionary motives]] and [[evolutionary game theory]].<ref name="Burum-2020" /> They argue that society rewards the act of giving but generally provides no motivation or incentive to give effectively. Past research suggests that altruistic motives are distorted by, among other things, [[parochialism]], [[Social status|status]] seeking and [[conformity]].<ref name="Nowak-2006" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Panchanathan |first1=Karthik |last2=Boyd |first2=Robert |date=November 2004 |title=Indirect reciprocity can stabilize cooperation without the second-order free rider problem |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/nature02978 |journal=Nature |language=en |volume=432 |issue=7016 |pages=499–502 |doi=10.1038/nature02978 |pmid=15565153 |bibcode=2004Natur.432..499P |s2cid=4373929 |issn=1476-4687}}</ref><ref name="Jaeger-2022" />
Humans are motivated to give, but not motivated to give effectively.<ref name="Burum-2020" /> In the domain of business decisions, investors look for how much return they will get for each dollar they invest. However, when it comes to the domain of altruistic decision-making, this line of thinking is far less common.<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011" /> In fact, most donors seem to prioritize giving to charitable organizations that spend the least possible amount on running costs in the hopes of having more of their donation reach the destination.<ref name="Lewis-2018" /><ref name="Caviola-2014">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Faulmüller |first2=Nadira |last3=Everett |first3=Jim A. C. |last4=Savulescu |first4=Julian |last5=Kahane |first5=Guy |date=July 2014 |title=The evaluability bias in charitable giving: Saving administration costs or saving lives? |url=https://www.proquest.com/docview/1548669952 |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=English |volume=9 |issue=4 |pages=303–315|doi=10.1017/S1930297500006185 |s2cid=18730753 |id={{ProQuest|1548669952}} |doi-access=free }}</ref>

== Evolutionary theory of ineffective altruism ==
While plenty of studies in the behavioral sciences have demonstrated the cognitive and emotional limitations in charitable giving, some argue that the reasons behind ineffective giving run deeper.<ref name="Jaeger-2022">{{Cite journal |last1=Jaeger |first1=Bastian |last2=van Vugt |first2=Mark |date=April 2022 |title=Psychological barriers to effective altruism: An evolutionary perspective |journal=Current Opinion in Psychology |volume=44 |pages=130–134 |doi=10.1016/j.copsyc.2021.09.008 |pmid=34628365 |s2cid=238582556 |via=Elsevier Science Direct|doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Burum-2020" /> A study by academics at [[Harvard University]] and the [[Massachusetts Institute of Technology]] suggested that the human tendency to be altruistically ineffective can be explained through [[evolution|evolutionary motives]] and [[evolutionary game theory|game theory]].<ref name="Burum-2020" /> They argue that society rewards the act of giving but provides no motivation or incentive to give effectively. Past research suggests that altruistic motives are distorted by, among other things, [[parochialism]], [[Social status|status]] and [[conformity]].<ref name="Nowak-2006" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Panchanathan |first1=Karthik |last2=Boyd |first2=Robert |date=November 2004 |title=Indirect reciprocity can stabilize cooperation without the second-order free rider problem |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/nature02978 |journal=Nature |language=en |volume=432 |issue=7016 |pages=499–502 |doi=10.1038/nature02978 |pmid=15565153 |bibcode=2004Natur.432..499P |s2cid=4373929 |issn=1476-4687}}</ref><ref name="Jaeger-2022" />


=== Parochialism ===
=== Parochialism ===
People are sensitive to effectiveness when they or their [[Kin selection|kin]] are at stake,<ref name="Nowak-2006">{{Cite journal |last=Nowak |first=M. A. |date=2006 |title=Five rules for the evolution of cooperation |journal=Science |volume=314 |issue=5805 |pages=1560–1563 |doi=10.1126/science.1133755 |pmid=17158317 |pmc=3279745 |bibcode=2006Sci...314.1560N }}</ref> but not so much when confronted with a needy stranger.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hamilton |first=W. D. |date=September 1963 |title=The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior |url=https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/497114 |journal=The American Naturalist |language=en |volume=97 |issue=896 |pages=354–356 |doi=10.1086/497114 |s2cid=84216415 |issn=0003-0147 |via=The University of Chicago Press Journals}}</ref><ref name="Darwin-1859">{{Cite book |last=Darwin |first=C. |title=On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life |publisher=P. F. Collier & Son |year=1859}}</ref> Donors have been shown to respond to impact and efficacy when giving to themselves, but less so when donating to charity.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref name="Jaeger-2022" /> In fact, while cost-effectiveness information of charities tends to be hard to evaluate,<ref name="Caviola-2020">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Schubert |first2=Stefan |last3=Nemirow |first3=Jason |date=March 2020 |title=The many obstacles to effective giving |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/judgment-and-decision-making/article/many-obstacles-to-effective-giving/09995867756FFAF8DD73430A393C021A |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=en |volume=15 |issue=2 |pages=159–172 |doi=10.1017/S1930297500007312 |issn=1930-2975 |via=CambridgeCore|doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Singer-2009" /> studies have shown that people are less [[Scope insensitivity|scope insensitive]] when the beneficiaries are family members.<ref name="Burum-2020" />
People are sensitive to effectiveness when they or their [[Kin selection|kin]] are at stake,<ref name="Nowak-2006">{{Cite journal |last=Nowak |first=M. A. |date=2006 |title=Five rules for the evolution of cooperation |journal=Science |volume=314 |issue=5805 |pages=1560–1563 |doi=10.1126/science.1133755 |pmid=17158317 |pmc=3279745 |bibcode=2006Sci...314.1560N }}</ref> but not so much when confronted with a needy stranger.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Hamilton |first=W. D. |date=September 1963 |title=The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior |url=https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/10.1086/497114 |journal=The American Naturalist |language=en |volume=97 |issue=896 |pages=354–356 |doi=10.1086/497114 |s2cid=84216415 |issn=0003-0147 |via=The University of Chicago Press Journals}}</ref><ref name="Darwin-1859">{{Cite book |last=Darwin |first=C. |title=On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life |publisher=P. F. Collier & Son |year=1859}}</ref> Donors have been shown to respond to impact and efficacy when giving to themselves, but less so when donating to charity.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref name="Jaeger-2022" /> While cost-effectiveness information of charities tends to be hard to evaluate,<ref name="Caviola-2020">{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Schubert |first2=Stefan |last3=Nemirow |first3=Jason |date=March 2020 |title=The many obstacles to effective giving |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/judgment-and-decision-making/article/many-obstacles-to-effective-giving/09995867756FFAF8DD73430A393C021A |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=en |volume=15 |issue=2 |pages=159–172 |doi=10.1017/S1930297500007312 |issn=1930-2975 |via=CambridgeCore|doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Singer-2009" /> studies have shown that people are less [[Scope insensitivity|scope insensitive]] when the beneficiaries are family members.<ref name="Burum-2020" />


Throughout human evolutionary history, residing in small, tightly-knit groups has given rise to prosocial emotions and intentions towards kin and ingroup members, rather than universally extending to those outside the group boundaries.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Aktipis |first1=Athena |last2=Cronk |first2=Lee |last3=Alcock |first3=Joe |last4=Ayers |first4=Jessica D. |last5=Baciu |first5=Cristina |last6=Balliet |first6=Daniel |last7=Boddy |first7=Amy M. |last8=Curry |first8=Oliver Scott |last9=Krems |first9=Jaimie Arona |last10=Muñoz |first10=Andrés |last11=Sullivan |first11=Daniel |last12=Sznycer |first12=Daniel |last13=Wilkinson |first13=Gerald S. |last14=Winfrey |first14=Pamela |date=July 2018 |title=Understanding cooperation through fitness interdependence |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/s41562-018-0378-4 |journal=Nature Human Behaviour |language=en |volume=2 |issue=7 |pages=429–431 |doi=10.1038/s41562-018-0378-4 |pmid=31097813 |s2cid=49667807 |issn=2397-3374|hdl=1871.1/72e0524e-788d-4f93-90f8-a6f04369a2a7 |hdl-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Greene-2013">{{Cite book |last=Greene |first=Joshua |title=Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them |publisher=Penguin Press |year=2013 |isbn=978-0-14-312605-8 |location=New York, NY |language=en}}</ref> Humans tend to exhibit [[Parochialism|parochial]] tendencies, showing concern for their [[In-group favoritism|in-groups]], but not [[In-group and out-group|out-groups]].<ref name="Jaeger-2022" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> This parochial inclination can hinder effective altruism, especially as a significant portion of human suffering occurs in distant regions.<ref name="Singer-2009">{{Cite book |last=Singer |first=Peter |title=The Life You Can Save: Acting Now to End World Poverty |publisher=Random House |year=2009 |isbn=978-1-4000-6710-7 |edition=1st |location=United States |language=en}}</ref><ref name="Bloom-2017">{{Cite journal |last=Bloom |first=Paul |date=January 2017 |title=Empathy and Its Discontents |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=21 |issue=1 |pages=24–31 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2016.11.004 |pmid=27916513 |s2cid=3863278 |issn=1364-6613 |via=Elsevier Science Direct}}</ref> Despite the potential impact of donations in different parts of the world, individuals in rich and developed countries often view assistance to physically distant others as less important than helping those in close proximity.<ref name="Bloom-2017" /><ref name="Jaeger-2022" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> Contrary to maximizing impact and effectiveness with their donations, many individuals commit to donating money to local charities and organizations to which they have a personal connection, thus living by the notion of "charity begins at home."<ref name="Berman-2018" /><ref>{{Cite web |last1=Adleberg |first1=Toni |last2=Surani |first2=Faiz |last3=GWWC |first3=Team |date=May 2021 |title=Charity begins at home; shouldn't we solve our own problems before helping others? |url=https://www.givingwhatwecan.org/blog/charity-begins-at-home-shouldnt-we-solve-our-own-problems-before-helping# |access-date=31 October 2023 |website=Giving What We Can}}</ref> Similarly, people are more inclined to help a needy child from their neighborhood rather than their city or country.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Kogut |first1=Tehila |last2=Ritov |first2=Ilana |last3=Rubaltelli |first3=Enrico |last4=Liberman |first4=Nira |date=September 2018 |title=How far is the suffering? The role of psychological distance and victims' identifiability in donation decisions |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/judgment-and-decision-making/article/how-far-is-the-suffering-the-role-of-psychological-distance-and-victims-identifiability-in-donation-decisions/72B0864A38305451E3F80CCE68D8BF72 |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=en |volume=13 |issue=5 |pages=458–466 |doi=10.1017/S1930297500008731 |issn=1930-2975 |via=CambridgeCore|doi-access=free }}</ref>
Throughout human evolutionary history, residing in small, tightly-knit groups has given rise to prosocial emotions and intentions towards kin and ingroup members, rather than universally extending to those outside the group boundaries.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Aktipis |first1=Athena |last2=Cronk |first2=Lee |last3=Alcock |first3=Joe |last4=Ayers |first4=Jessica D. |last5=Baciu |first5=Cristina |last6=Balliet |first6=Daniel |last7=Boddy |first7=Amy M. |last8=Curry |first8=Oliver Scott |last9=Krems |first9=Jaimie Arona |last10=Muñoz |first10=Andrés |last11=Sullivan |first11=Daniel |last12=Sznycer |first12=Daniel |last13=Wilkinson |first13=Gerald S. |last14=Winfrey |first14=Pamela |date=July 2018 |title=Understanding cooperation through fitness interdependence |url=https://www.nature.com/articles/s41562-018-0378-4 |journal=Nature Human Behaviour |language=en |volume=2 |issue=7 |pages=429–431 |doi=10.1038/s41562-018-0378-4 |pmid=31097813 |s2cid=49667807 |issn=2397-3374|hdl=1871.1/72e0524e-788d-4f93-90f8-a6f04369a2a7 |hdl-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Greene-2013">{{Cite book |last=Greene |first=Joshua |title=Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them |publisher=Penguin Press |year=2013 |isbn=978-0-14-312605-8 |location=New York, NY |language=en}}</ref> Humans tend to exhibit [[Parochialism|parochial]] tendencies, showing concern for their [[In-group favoritism|in-groups]], but not [[In-group and out-group|out-groups]].<ref name="Jaeger-2022" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> This parochial inclination can hinder effective altruism, especially as a significant portion of human suffering occurs in distant regions.<ref name="Singer-2009">{{Cite book |last=Singer |first=Peter |title=The Life You Can Save: Acting Now to End World Poverty |publisher=Random House |year=2009 |isbn=978-1-4000-6710-7 |edition=1st |location=United States |language=en}}</ref><ref name="Bloom-2017">{{Cite journal |last=Bloom |first=Paul |date=January 2017 |title=Empathy and Its Discontents |journal=Trends in Cognitive Sciences |volume=21 |issue=1 |pages=24–31 |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2016.11.004 |pmid=27916513 |s2cid=3863278 |issn=1364-6613 |via=Elsevier Science Direct}}</ref> Despite the potential impact of donations in different parts of the world, individuals in rich and developed countries often view assistance to physically distant others as less important than helping those in close proximity.<ref name="Bloom-2017" /><ref name="Jaeger-2022" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> Contrary to maximizing impact and effectiveness with their donations, many individuals commit to donating money to local charities and organizations to which they have a personal connection, thus living by the notion of "charity begins at home".<ref name="Berman-2018" /><ref>{{Cite web |last1=Adleberg |first1=Toni |last2=Surani |first2=Faiz |last3=GWWC |first3=Team |date=May 2021 |title=Charity begins at home; shouldn't we solve our own problems before helping others? |url=https://www.givingwhatwecan.org/blog/charity-begins-at-home-shouldnt-we-solve-our-own-problems-before-helping# |access-date=31 October 2023 |website=Giving What We Can}}</ref> Similarly, people are more inclined to help a needy child from their neighborhood rather than their city or country.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Kogut |first1=Tehila |last2=Ritov |first2=Ilana |last3=Rubaltelli |first3=Enrico |last4=Liberman |first4=Nira |date=September 2018 |title=How far is the suffering? The role of psychological distance and victims' identifiability in donation decisions |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/judgment-and-decision-making/article/how-far-is-the-suffering-the-role-of-psychological-distance-and-victims-identifiability-in-donation-decisions/72B0864A38305451E3F80CCE68D8BF72 |journal=Judgment and Decision Making |language=en |volume=13 |issue=5 |pages=458–466 |doi=10.1017/S1930297500008731 |issn=1930-2975 |via=CambridgeCore|doi-access=free }}</ref>


=== Status ===
=== Status seeking ===
Humans assign value to their [[social status]] within a group for survival and reproduction.<ref name="Darwin-1859" /> People tend to pursue high-status positions to enjoy benefits, such as desirable mating partners.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=von Rueden |first1=Christopher R. |last2=Jaeggi |first2=Adrian V. |date=2016-09-27 |title=Men's status and reproductive success in 33 nonindustrial societies: Effects of subsistence, marriage system, and reproductive strategy |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=113 |issue=39 |pages=10824–10829 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1606800113 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=5047206 |pmid=27601650 |bibcode=2016PNAS..11310824V |doi-access=free }}</ref> Therefore, behaviors that can produce reputational benefits are desirable to enhance one's standing in society.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Schaller |first1=Mark |last2=Kenrick |first2=Douglas T. |last3=Neel |first3=Rebecca |last4=Neuberg |first4=Steven L. |date=June 2017 |title=Evolution and human motivation: A fundamental motives framework |url=https://compass.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/spc3.12319 |journal=Social and Personality Psychology Compass |language=en |volume=11 |issue=6 |doi=10.1111/spc3.12319 |issn=1751-9004 |via=Wiley}}</ref> Altruistic acts are generally viewed positively,<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Durkee |first1=Patrick K. |last2=Lukaszewski |first2=Aaron W. |last3=Buss |first3=David M. |date=September 2020 |title=Psychological foundations of human status allocation |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=117 |issue=35 |pages=21235–21241 |doi=10.1073/pnas.2006148117 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=7474695 |pmid=32817486 |bibcode=2020PNAS..11721235D |doi-access=free }}</ref> yield social rewards,<ref name="Nowak-2006" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> and are cumulative.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Ashraf |first1=Nava |last2=Bandiera |first2=Oriana |date=May 2017 |title=Altruistic Capital |url=https://www.aeaweb.org/articles?id=10.1257/aer.p20171097 |journal=American Economic Review |language=en |volume=107 |issue=5 |pages=70–75 |doi=10.1257/aer.p20171097 |issn=0002-8282 |via=American Economic Association}}</ref> However, ''effective'' altruism, that is, altruistic behavior that focuses on maximizing others' welfare, is not socially rewarded.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Yudkin |first1=Daniel A. |last2=Prosser |first2=Annayah M. B. |last3=Crockett |first3=Molly J. |date=October 2019 |title=Actions speak louder than outcomes in judgments of prosocial behavior. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/emo0000514 |journal=Emotion |language=en |volume=19 |issue=7 |pages=1138–1147 |doi=10.1037/emo0000514 |pmid=30475039 |s2cid=53746918 |issn=1931-1516}}</ref> In fact, evidence-based reasoning in charitable giving is perceived negatively, [[Amorality|amoral]], and reduces a person's [[likability]].<ref>{{Cite web |last1=Montealegre |first1=Andres |last2=Bush |first2=Lance |last3=Moss |first3=David |last4=Pizarro |first4=David |last5=Jimenez-Leal |first5=William |date=2023 |title=Does Maximizing Good Make People Look Bad? |url=https://osf.io/preprints/psyarxiv/2zbax/ |access-date=2023-11-22 |website=osf.io}}</ref> Some have even argued that the reputational costs incurred for engaging in effective giving explain people's aversion to prioritizing some causes over more impactful ones.<ref name="Caviola-2021" />
Humans assign value to their [[social status]] within a group for survival and reproduction.<ref name="Darwin-1859" /> People tend to pursue high-status positions to enjoy benefits, such as desirable mating partners.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=von Rueden |first1=Christopher R. |last2=Jaeggi |first2=Adrian V. |date=2016-09-27 |title=Men's status and reproductive success in 33 nonindustrial societies: Effects of subsistence, marriage system, and reproductive strategy |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=113 |issue=39 |pages=10824–10829 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1606800113 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=5047206 |pmid=27601650 |bibcode=2016PNAS..11310824V |doi-access=free }}</ref> Therefore, behaviors that can produce reputational benefits are desirable to enhance one's standing in society.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Schaller |first1=Mark |last2=Kenrick |first2=Douglas T. |last3=Neel |first3=Rebecca |last4=Neuberg |first4=Steven L. |date=June 2017 |title=Evolution and human motivation: A fundamental motives framework |url=https://compass.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/spc3.12319 |journal=Social and Personality Psychology Compass |language=en |volume=11 |issue=6 |doi=10.1111/spc3.12319 |issn=1751-9004 |via=Wiley}}</ref> Altruistic acts are generally viewed positively,<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Durkee |first1=Patrick K. |last2=Lukaszewski |first2=Aaron W. |last3=Buss |first3=David M. |date=September 2020 |title=Psychological foundations of human status allocation |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=117 |issue=35 |pages=21235–21241 |doi=10.1073/pnas.2006148117 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=7474695 |pmid=32817486 |bibcode=2020PNAS..11721235D |doi-access=free }}</ref> yield social rewards,<ref name="Nowak-2006" /><ref name="Burum-2020" /> and are cumulative.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Ashraf |first1=Nava |last2=Bandiera |first2=Oriana |date=May 2017 |title=Altruistic Capital |url=https://www.aeaweb.org/articles?id=10.1257/aer.p20171097 |journal=American Economic Review |language=en |volume=107 |issue=5 |pages=70–75 |doi=10.1257/aer.p20171097 |issn=0002-8282 |via=American Economic Association}}</ref> However, ''effective'' altruism, that is, altruistic behavior that focuses on maximizing others' welfare, is often not socially rewarded.<ref name="Burum-2020" /><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Yudkin |first1=Daniel A. |last2=Prosser |first2=Annayah M. B. |last3=Crockett |first3=Molly J. |date=October 2019 |title=Actions speak louder than outcomes in judgments of prosocial behavior. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/emo0000514 |journal=Emotion |language=en |volume=19 |issue=7 |pages=1138–1147 |doi=10.1037/emo0000514 |pmid=30475039 |s2cid=53746918 |issn=1931-1516}}</ref> Evidence-based reasoning in charitable giving may be perceived negatively, as [[Amorality|amoral]], and so will reduce a person's [[likability]].<ref>{{Cite web |last1=Montealegre |first1=Andres |last2=Bush |first2=Lance |last3=Moss |first3=David |last4=Pizarro |first4=David |last5=Jimenez-Leal |first5=William |date=2023 |title=Does Maximizing Good Make People Look Bad? |url=https://osf.io/preprints/psyarxiv/2zbax/ |access-date=2023-11-22 |website=osf.io}}</ref> Some have even argued that the reputational costs incurred for engaging in effective giving explain people's aversion to prioritizing some causes over more impactful ones.<ref name="Caviola-2021" />


=== Conformity ===
=== Conformity ===
Many living organisms have demonstrated [[conformity]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Boyd |first1=Robert |last2=Richerson |first2=Peter J. |last3=Henrich |first3=Joseph |date=2011-06-28 |title=The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=108 |issue= Suppl 2|pages=10918–10925 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1100290108 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=3131818 |pmid=21690340 |bibcode=2011PNAS..10810918B |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Muthukrishna |first1=Michael |last2=Morgan |first2=Thomas J. H. |last3=Henrich |first3=Joseph |date=2016-01-01 |title=The when and who of social learning and conformist transmission |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1090513815000586 |journal=Evolution and Human Behavior |volume=37 |issue=1 |pages=10–20 |doi=10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.05.004 |issn=1090-5138}}</ref> that is, the tendency to use dominant group norms (or [[descriptive norms]]) as guiding rules of behavior. Research on humans has also shown that [[social norm]]s have the power to influence what others do.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Pike |first1=Thomas W. |last2=Laland |first2=Kevin N. |date=2010-08-23 |title=Conformist learning in nine-spined sticklebacks' foraging decisions |journal=Biology Letters |language=en |volume=6 |issue=4 |pages=466–468 |doi=10.1098/rsbl.2009.1014 |issn=1744-9561 |pmc=2936200 |pmid=20129948}}</ref> In the judgment and decision-making research, this observation has come to be known as the [[bandwagon effect]]. The power of this bias has also been demonstrated in the field of charitable giving. In fact, people have been shown to donate more, or to exhibit an increased likelihood to donate, when they perceived donating to charity as the social norm or the [[Default effect|default choice]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Everett |first1=Jim A.C. |last2=Caviola |first2=Lucius |last3=Kahane |first3=Guy |last4=Savulescu |first4=Julian |last5=Faber |first5=Nadira S. |date=March 2015 |title=Doing good by doing nothing? The role of social norms in explaining default effects in altruistic contexts |journal=European Journal of Social Psychology |language=en |volume=45 |issue=2 |pages=230–241 |doi=10.1002/ejsp.2080 |issn=0046-2772 |doi-access=free }}</ref> Therefore, the fact that many people become increasingly in favor of donating to ineffective options, then society will see the creation of a norm for people to give ineffectively.<ref name="Jaeger-2022" /> As a result, people rely more strongly on their intuitions<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Croson |first1=Rachel |last2=Handy |first2=Femida |last3=Shang |first3=Jen |date=June 2009 |title=Keeping up with the Joneses: The relationship of perceived descriptive social norms, social information, and charitable giving |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/nml.232 |journal=Nonprofit Management and Leadership |language=en |volume=19 |issue=4 |pages=467–489 |doi=10.1002/nml.232 |issn=1048-6682}}</ref> which lead them to choosing to give ineffectively simply because they know that most others would do the same thing.<ref name="Jaeger-2022" />
Many living organisms have demonstrated [[conformity]],<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Boyd |first1=Robert |last2=Richerson |first2=Peter J. |last3=Henrich |first3=Joseph |date=2011-06-28 |title=The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences |language=en |volume=108 |issue= Suppl 2|pages=10918–10925 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1100290108 |issn=0027-8424 |pmc=3131818 |pmid=21690340 |bibcode=2011PNAS..10810918B |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Muthukrishna |first1=Michael |last2=Morgan |first2=Thomas J. H. |last3=Henrich |first3=Joseph |date=2016-01-01 |title=The when and who of social learning and conformist transmission |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S1090513815000586 |journal=Evolution and Human Behavior |volume=37 |issue=1 |pages=10–20 |doi=10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.05.004 |issn=1090-5138}}</ref> that is, the tendency to use dominant group norms (or descriptive norms) as guiding rules of behavior. Research on humans has also shown that [[social norm]]s have the power to influence what others do.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Pike |first1=Thomas W. |last2=Laland |first2=Kevin N. |date=2010-08-23 |title=Conformist learning in nine-spined sticklebacks' foraging decisions |journal=Biology Letters |language=en |volume=6 |issue=4 |pages=466–468 |doi=10.1098/rsbl.2009.1014 |issn=1744-9561 |pmc=2936200 |pmid=20129948}}</ref> In the judgment and decision-making research, this observation has come to be known as the [[bandwagon effect]]. The power of this bias has also been demonstrated in the field of charitable giving. In fact, people have been shown to donate more, or to exhibit an increased likelihood to donate, when they perceived donating to charity as the social norm or the [[Default effect|default choice]].<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Everett |first1=Jim A.C. |last2=Caviola |first2=Lucius |last3=Kahane |first3=Guy |last4=Savulescu |first4=Julian |last5=Faber |first5=Nadira S. |date=March 2015 |title=Doing good by doing nothing? The role of social norms in explaining default effects in altruistic contexts |journal=European Journal of Social Psychology |language=en |volume=45 |issue=2 |pages=230–241 |doi=10.1002/ejsp.2080 |issn=0046-2772 |doi-access=free }}</ref> Therefore, the fact that many people become increasingly in favor of donating to ineffective options, then society will see the creation of a norm for people to give ineffectively.<ref name="Jaeger-2022" /> As a result, people rely more strongly on their intuitions<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Croson |first1=Rachel |last2=Handy |first2=Femida |last3=Shang |first3=Jen |date=June 2009 |title=Keeping up with the Joneses: The relationship of perceived descriptive social norms, social information, and charitable giving |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/nml.232 |journal=Nonprofit Management and Leadership |language=en |volume=19 |issue=4 |pages=467–489 |doi=10.1002/nml.232 |issn=1048-6682}}</ref> which lead them to choosing to give ineffectively simply because they know that most others would do the same thing.<ref name="Jaeger-2022" />

== Obstacles to effective giving ==


=== Motivational obstacles ===
== Motivational obstacles ==


==== Subjectivity ====
=== Subjective preferences ===
People often prioritize giving to charities that align with their subjectively preferred causes.<ref name="Berman-2018">{{Cite journal |last1=Berman |first1=Jonathan Z. |last2=Barasch |first2=Alixandra |last3=Levine |first3=Emma E. |last4=Small |first4=Deborah A. |date=May 2018 |title=Impediments to Effective Altruism: The Role of Subjective Preferences in Charitable Giving |url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0956797617747648 |journal=Psychological Science |language=en |volume=29 |issue=5 |pages=834–844 |doi=10.1177/0956797617747648 |pmid=29659341 |s2cid=4901791 |issn=0956-7976 |via=Association for Psychological Science}}</ref> Commonly, people believe charity to be a subjective decision which should not be motivated by numbers, but by care for the cause. This aligns with the theory of [[warm-glow giving]] originally proposed by the economist [[James Andreoni]]. According to Andreoni (1990), individuals gain satisfaction from the act of giving but are not concerned about the benefits generated by their act.<ref name="Andreoni-1990">{{Cite journal |last=Andreoni |first=James |date=1990 |title=Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving. |journal=The Economic Journal |volume=100 |issue=401 |pages=464–477|doi=10.2307/2234133 |jstor=2234133 |s2cid=6001457 }}</ref><ref name="Berman-2018" />
People often prioritize giving to charities that align with their subjectively preferred causes.<ref name="Berman-2018">{{Cite journal |last1=Berman |first1=Jonathan Z. |last2=Barasch |first2=Alixandra |last3=Levine |first3=Emma E. |last4=Small |first4=Deborah A. |date=May 2018 |title=Impediments to Effective Altruism: The Role of Subjective Preferences in Charitable Giving |url=http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/0956797617747648 |journal=Psychological Science |language=en |volume=29 |issue=5 |pages=834–844 |doi=10.1177/0956797617747648 |pmid=29659341 |s2cid=4901791 |issn=0956-7976 |via=Association for Psychological Science}}</ref> Commonly, people believe charity to be a subjective decision which should not be motivated by numbers, but by care for the cause. This aligns with the theory of [[warm-glow giving]] originally proposed by the economist [[James Andreoni]]. According to Andreoni (1990), individuals gain satisfaction from the act of giving but are not concerned about the benefits generated by their act.<ref name="Andreoni-1990">{{Cite journal |last=Andreoni |first=James |date=1990 |title=Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving. |journal=The Economic Journal |volume=100 |issue=401 |pages=464–477|doi=10.2307/2234133 |jstor=2234133 |s2cid=6001457 }}</ref><ref name="Berman-2018" />


==== Narrow moral circle ====
=== Narrow moral circle ===
[[Moral circle expansion]] is the concept of increasing one's number and kind of subjects deserving of moral concern over time.<ref name="Anthis-2021">{{Cite journal |last1=Anthis |first1=Jacy Reese |last2=Paez |first2=Eze |date=2021-06-01 |title=Moral circle expansion: A promising strategy to impact the far future |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0016328721000641 |journal=Futures |volume=130 |pages=102756 |doi=10.1016/j.futures.2021.102756 |issn=0016-3287|doi-access=free }}</ref> The establishment of one's moral circle depends on spatial, biological, and temporal proximity.<ref name="Anthis-2021" /><ref name="Caviola-2021" /> For instance, many donors in [[Western Educated Industrialized Rich Democratic|WEIRD]] countries tend to favor charities that conduct work within their respective geographical boundaries.<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011" /> In terms of biological distance, people favor donating money to help humans instead of animals, even in cases when animals can have equal cognitive and suffering capacities.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Everett |first2=Jim A. C. |last3=Faber |first3=Nadira S. |date=June 2019 |title=The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/pspp0000182 |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |language=en |volume=116 |issue=6 |pages=1011–1029 |doi=10.1037/pspp0000182 |pmid=29517258 |s2cid=3818419 |issn=1939-1315}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Kahane |first2=Guy |last3=Everett |first3=Jim A. C. |last4=Teperman |first4=Elliot |last5=Savulescu |first5=Julian |last6=Faber |first6=Nadira S. |date=May 2021 |title=Utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people? Harming animals and humans for the greater good. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/xge0000988 |journal=Journal of Experimental Psychology: General |language=en |volume=150 |issue=5 |pages=1008–1039 |doi=10.1037/xge0000988 |pmid=33074696 |issn=1939-2222}}</ref> The idea of temporal proximity relates to people's tendency to prefer helping current generations over future ones.<ref>{{Cite book |last=MacAskill |first=William |title=What We Owe the Future |publisher=Basic Books |year=2022 |isbn=978-1541618626 |edition=1st |language=en}}</ref><ref name="Caviola-2021" />
[[Moral circle expansion]] is the concept of increasing one's number and kind of subjects deserving of moral concern over time.<ref name="Anthis-2021">{{Cite journal |last1=Anthis |first1=Jacy Reese |last2=Paez |first2=Eze |date=2021-06-01 |title=Moral circle expansion: A promising strategy to impact the far future |url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0016328721000641 |journal=Futures |volume=130 |pages=102756 |doi=10.1016/j.futures.2021.102756 |issn=0016-3287|doi-access=free }}</ref> The establishment of one's moral circle depends on spatial, biological, and temporal proximity.<ref name="Anthis-2021" /><ref name="Caviola-2021" /> For instance, many donors in [[Western Educated Industrialized Rich Democratic|WEIRD]] countries tend to favor charities that conduct work within their respective geographical boundaries.<ref name="The Science of Giving-2011" /> In terms of biological distance, people favor donating money to help humans instead of animals, even in cases when animals can have equal cognitive and suffering capacities.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Everett |first2=Jim A. C. |last3=Faber |first3=Nadira S. |date=June 2019 |title=The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/pspp0000182 |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |language=en |volume=116 |issue=6 |pages=1011–1029 |doi=10.1037/pspp0000182 |pmid=29517258 |s2cid=3818419 |issn=1939-1315}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Caviola |first1=Lucius |last2=Kahane |first2=Guy |last3=Everett |first3=Jim A. C. |last4=Teperman |first4=Elliot |last5=Savulescu |first5=Julian |last6=Faber |first6=Nadira S. |date=May 2021 |title=Utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people? Harming animals and humans for the greater good. |url=http://doi.apa.org/getdoi.cfm?doi=10.1037/xge0000988 |journal=Journal of Experimental Psychology: General |language=en |volume=150 |issue=5 |pages=1008–1039 |doi=10.1037/xge0000988 |pmid=33074696 |issn=1939-2222}}</ref> The idea of temporal proximity relates to people's tendency to prefer helping current generations over future ones.<ref>{{Cite book |last=MacAskill |first=William |title=What We Owe the Future |publisher=Basic Books |year=2022 |isbn=978-1541618626 |edition=1st |language=en}}</ref><ref name="Caviola-2021" />


==== Scope neglect (Insensitivity) ====
=== Scope neglect (insensitivity) ===
[[Scope neglect]] (or ''scope insensitivity'') is the idea that people are numb to the number of victims in large, high-stake humanitarian situations.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Yudkowsky |first=Eliezer |date=13 May 2007 |title=Scope Insensitivity |url=https://www.lesswrong.com/posts/2ftJ38y9SRBCBsCzy/scope-insensitivity |archive-url= |access-date=16 October 2023 |website=lesswrong.com}}</ref><ref name="Dickert-2015">{{Cite journal |last1=Dickert |first1=Stephan |last2=Västfjäll |first2=Daniel |last3=Kleber |first3=Janet |last4=Slovic |first4=Paul |date=September 2015 |title=Scope insensitivity: The limits of intuitive valuation of human lives in public policy. |journal=Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition |language=en |volume=4 |issue=3 |pages=248–255 |doi=10.1016/j.jarmac.2014.09.002 |issn=2211-369X|doi-access=free }}</ref> Some research has compared this [[cognitive bias]] to the economic concept of [[diminishing marginal utility]] wherein people demonstrate a decreasing non-linear concern for individuals as the number of people increases.<ref name="Dickert-2015" />
[[Scope neglect]] (or ''scope insensitivity'') is the idea that people are numb to the number of victims in large, high-stake humanitarian situations.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Yudkowsky |first=Eliezer |date=13 May 2007 |title=Scope Insensitivity |url=https://www.lesswrong.com/posts/2ftJ38y9SRBCBsCzy/scope-insensitivity |archive-url= |access-date=16 October 2023 |website=lesswrong.com}}</ref><ref name="Dickert-2015">{{Cite journal |last1=Dickert |first1=Stephan |last2=Västfjäll |first2=Daniel |last3=Kleber |first3=Janet |last4=Slovic |first4=Paul |date=September 2015 |title=Scope insensitivity: The limits of intuitive valuation of human lives in public policy. |journal=Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition |language=en |volume=4 |issue=3 |pages=248–255 |doi=10.1016/j.jarmac.2014.09.002 |issn=2211-369X|doi-access=free }}</ref> Some research has compared this [[cognitive bias]] to the economic concept of [[diminishing marginal utility]] wherein people demonstrate a decreasing non-linear concern for individuals as the number of people increases.<ref name="Dickert-2015" />


=== Epistemic obstacles ===
== Epistemic obstacles ==


==== Overhead aversion ====
=== Overhead aversion ===
Donors are averse to giving charities that devote a lot of their expenses to administration<ref name="Gneezy-2014">{{Cite journal |last1=Gneezy |first1=U. |last2=Keenan |first2=E. A. |last3=Gneezy |first3=A. |date=2014-10-30 |title=Avoiding overhead aversion in charity |journal=Science |volume=346 |issue=6209 |pages=632–635 |doi=10.1126/science.1253932 |pmid=25359974 |bibcode=2014Sci...346..632G |s2cid=206557384 |issn=0036-8075}}</ref> or running costs.<ref name="Caviola-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2020" /> Several studies have demonstrated the ubiquitous effect of [[Uri Gneezy|overhead aversion]] which is commonly attributed to people's conflation between overhead spending and charity cost-effectiveness (or impact).<ref name="Gneezy-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2020" /> Furthermore, some have argued that when donors learn that a charity uses their donation to fund running costs, donors experience a diminished feeling of warm-glow,<ref name="Andreoni-1990" /> which is a significant driver of donation behavior.<ref name="Gneezy-2014" />
Donors are averse to giving charities that devote a lot of their expenses to administration<ref name="Gneezy-2014">{{Cite journal |last1=Gneezy |first1=U. |last2=Keenan |first2=E. A. |last3=Gneezy |first3=A. |date=2014-10-30 |title=Avoiding overhead aversion in charity |journal=Science |volume=346 |issue=6209 |pages=632–635 |doi=10.1126/science.1253932 |pmid=25359974 |bibcode=2014Sci...346..632G |s2cid=206557384 |issn=0036-8075}}</ref> or running costs.<ref name="Caviola-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2020" /> Several studies have demonstrated the ubiquitous effect of [[Uri Gneezy|overhead aversion]] which is commonly attributed to people's conflation between overhead spending and charity cost-effectiveness (or impact).<ref name="Gneezy-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2014" /><ref name="Caviola-2020" /> Furthermore, some have argued that when donors learn that a charity uses their donation to fund running costs, donors experience a diminished feeling of warm-glow,<ref name="Andreoni-1990" /> which is a significant driver of donation behavior.<ref name="Gneezy-2014" />


==== Quantifiability scepticism ====
=== Quantifiability scepticism ===
[[File:QALY graph-en.svg|thumb|320px|Demonstration of quality-adjusted life years (QALYs) for two individuals. Individual A (who did not receive an intervention) has fewer QALYs than individual B (who received an intervention).]]
[[File:QALY graph-en.svg|thumb|320px|Demonstration of quality-adjusted life years (QALYs) for two individuals. Individual A (who did not receive an intervention) has fewer QALYs than individual B (who received an intervention).]]


Intangible outcomes (such as health interventions, charity effectiveness) are hard to quantify, and many people doubt that they can every be quantified and compared.<ref name="Caviola-2021" /> However, in disciplines such as [[health economics]], health outcomes and interventions are quantified and evaluated using metrics such as [[Quality-adjusted life year|quality-adjusted life years (QALYs)]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Banerjee |first=Abhijit V. |title=Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty |last2=Duflo |first2=Esther |publisher=PublicAffairs |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-58648-798-0 |location=United States |language=en}}</ref> In a similar vein, [[Happiness economics|happiness economists]] have developed the concept of [[WELLBY|wellbeing-years (WELLBYs)]] which evaluates effectiveness in terms of life-years lived up to full life satisfaction.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=De Neve |first=Jan-Emmanuel |last2=Clark |first2=Andrew E. |last3=Krekel |first3=Christian |last4=Layard |first4=Richard |last5=O’Donnell |first5=Gus |date=2020-10-05 |title=Taking a wellbeing years approach to policy choice |url=https://www.bmj.com/content/371/bmj.m3853 |journal=BMJ |language=en |volume=371 |pages=m3853 |doi=10.1136/bmj.m3853 |issn=1756-1833 |pmid=33020062}}</ref> Put simply, a WELLBY is given by:<math display="block">WELLBY = { L \times\Delta W }</math>Where <math>L</math> is the number of lives remaining from the region's life expectancy and <math>\Delta W</math> is the change in life satisfaction expected to result from a particular action or intervention.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Treasury |first=HM |date=2021 |title=Wellbeing Guidance for Appraisal: Supplementary Green Book Guidance |url=https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/1005388/Wellbeing_guidance_for_appraisal_-_supplementary_Green_Book_guidance.pdf |url-status=live |access-date=11 November 2023 |website=HM Treasury}}</ref> Thus, charity cost-effectiveness analyses use a number of different measures grounded in academic research to quantify their impact, allowing direct comparisons of charities that address multiple causes.<ref name="Caviola-2021" />
Intangible outcomes (such as health interventions, charity effectiveness) are hard to quantify, and many people doubt that they can every be quantified and compared.<ref name="Caviola-2021" /> However, in disciplines such as [[health economics]], health outcomes and interventions are quantified and evaluated using metrics such as [[Quality-adjusted life year|quality-adjusted life years (QALYs)]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Banerjee |first=Abhijit V. |title=Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty |last2=Duflo |first2=Esther |publisher=PublicAffairs |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-58648-798-0 |location=United States |language=en}}</ref> In a similar vein, [[Happiness economics|happiness economists]] have developed the concept of [[WELLBY|wellbeing-years (WELLBYs)]] which evaluates effectiveness in terms of life-years lived up to full life satisfaction.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=De Neve |first=Jan-Emmanuel |last2=Clark |first2=Andrew E. |last3=Krekel |first3=Christian |last4=Layard |first4=Richard |last5=O’Donnell |first5=Gus |date=2020-10-05 |title=Taking a wellbeing years approach to policy choice |url=https://www.bmj.com/content/371/bmj.m3853 |journal=BMJ |language=en |volume=371 |pages=m3853 |doi=10.1136/bmj.m3853 |issn=1756-1833 |pmid=33020062}}</ref> Put simply, a WELLBY is given by:<math display="block">WELLBY = { L \times\Delta W }</math>Where <math>L</math> is the number of lives remaining from the region's life expectancy and <math>\Delta W</math> is the change in life satisfaction expected to result from a particular action or intervention.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Treasury |first=HM |date=2021 |title=Wellbeing Guidance for Appraisal: Supplementary Green Book Guidance |url=https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/1005388/Wellbeing_guidance_for_appraisal_-_supplementary_Green_Book_guidance.pdf |url-status=live |access-date=11 November 2023 |website=HM Treasury}}</ref> Thus, charity cost-effectiveness analyses use a number of different measures grounded in academic research to quantify their impact, allowing direct comparisons of charities that address multiple causes.<ref name="Caviola-2021" />


==== Ignorance about effective charities ====
=== Ignorance about more effective options ===
The [[effective altruism]] movement does substantial work on identifying the world's most effective charities through charity evaluators such as [[GiveWell]], [[Giving What We Can]], and [[Animal Charity Evaluators]]. However, many people are unaware of these organizations and the charities they evaluate,<ref name="Caviola-2020" /> and are strongly driven by emotional responses when estimating the effectiveness of a charity;<ref name="Caviola-2020" /> choosing instead to prioritize those causes to which they have a personal connection.<ref name="Berman-2018" />
The [[effective altruism]] movement does substantial work on identifying the world's most effective charities through charity evaluators such as [[GiveWell]], [[Giving What We Can]], and [[Animal Charity Evaluators]]. However, many people are unaware of these organizations and the charities they evaluate,<ref name="Caviola-2020" /> and are strongly driven by emotional responses when estimating the effectiveness of a charity;<ref name="Caviola-2020" /> choosing instead to prioritize those causes to which they have a personal connection.<ref name="Berman-2018" />


Line 60: Line 56:
{{Portal|Psychology|Society}}
{{Portal|Psychology|Society}}
{{columns-list|colwidth=22em|
{{columns-list|colwidth=22em|
* [[Altruism]]
* [[Altruism (ethics)]]
* [[Altruism (ethics)]]
* [[Bandwagon effect]]
* [[Charitable organization]]
* [[Charitable organization]]
* [[Charity (practice)]]
* [[Effective altruism]]
* [[Evidence-based policy]]
* [[Evidence-based policy]]
* [[Evolution]]
* [[List of cognitive biases]]
* [[List of cognitive biases]]
* [[Moral psychology]]
* [[Moral psychology]]

Revision as of 22:43, 20 December 2023

Peter Singer is one of the prominent philosophers of effective altruism.

In the philosophy of effective altruism, an altruistic act such as charitable giving is considered more effective, or cost-effective, if it uses a set of resources to do more good per unit of resource than other options, with the goal of trying to do the most good.[1] Following this definition of effectiveness, researchers in psychology and related fields have identified barriers to effective altruism that can cause people to choose less effective options when they engage in altruistic activities such as charitable giving.[2][3][4] Such barriers can include the evolutionary predispositions of parochialism, status seeking, and conformity; the motivational obstacles of subjective preferences, a narrow moral circle, and scope neglect; and the epistemic obstacles of overhead aversion, quantifiability skepticism, and ignorance about more effective options.

Overview

In general, humans are motivated to do good things in the world, whether that is through donations to charity, volunteering time for a cause, or just lending a hand to someone who needs help.[5][6] In 2022, approximately 4.2 billion people donated their money, time, or helped a stranger.[5] Donating money to charity is especially substantial. For instance, 2% of the GDP of the United States goes to charitable organizations—a total of more than $450 billion in annual donations.[7] Despite the human tendency and motivation to give and engage in altruistic behavior, research has shed light on an unequal motivation to give effectively.[4]

Humans are motivated to give, but often not motivated to give effectively.[3] In the domain of business decisions, investors look for how much return they will get for each dollar they invest. However, when it comes to the domain of altruistic decision-making, this line of thinking is far less common.[2] Most donors seem to prioritize giving to charitable organizations that spend the least possible amount on running costs in the hopes of having more of their donation reach the destination.[8][9]

Evolutionary predispositions

While plenty of studies in the behavioral sciences have demonstrated the cognitive and emotional limitations in charitable giving, some argue that the reasons behind ineffective giving run deeper.[10][3] A study by academics at Harvard University and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology suggested that the human tendency to be altruistically ineffective can be explained through evolutionary motives and evolutionary game theory.[3] They argue that society rewards the act of giving but generally provides no motivation or incentive to give effectively. Past research suggests that altruistic motives are distorted by, among other things, parochialism, status seeking and conformity.[11][12][10]

Parochialism

People are sensitive to effectiveness when they or their kin are at stake,[11] but not so much when confronted with a needy stranger.[3][13][14] Donors have been shown to respond to impact and efficacy when giving to themselves, but less so when donating to charity.[3][10] While cost-effectiveness information of charities tends to be hard to evaluate,[15][16] studies have shown that people are less scope insensitive when the beneficiaries are family members.[3]

Throughout human evolutionary history, residing in small, tightly-knit groups has given rise to prosocial emotions and intentions towards kin and ingroup members, rather than universally extending to those outside the group boundaries.[17][18] Humans tend to exhibit parochial tendencies, showing concern for their in-groups, but not out-groups.[10][3] This parochial inclination can hinder effective altruism, especially as a significant portion of human suffering occurs in distant regions.[16][19] Despite the potential impact of donations in different parts of the world, individuals in rich and developed countries often view assistance to physically distant others as less important than helping those in close proximity.[19][10][3] Contrary to maximizing impact and effectiveness with their donations, many individuals commit to donating money to local charities and organizations to which they have a personal connection, thus living by the notion of "charity begins at home".[20][21] Similarly, people are more inclined to help a needy child from their neighborhood rather than their city or country.[22]

Status seeking

Humans assign value to their social status within a group for survival and reproduction.[14] People tend to pursue high-status positions to enjoy benefits, such as desirable mating partners.[23] Therefore, behaviors that can produce reputational benefits are desirable to enhance one's standing in society.[24] Altruistic acts are generally viewed positively,[25] yield social rewards,[11][3] and are cumulative.[26] However, effective altruism, that is, altruistic behavior that focuses on maximizing others' welfare, is often not socially rewarded.[3][27] Evidence-based reasoning in charitable giving may be perceived negatively, as amoral, and so will reduce a person's likability.[28] Some have even argued that the reputational costs incurred for engaging in effective giving explain people's aversion to prioritizing some causes over more impactful ones.[4]

Conformity

Many living organisms have demonstrated conformity,[29][30] that is, the tendency to use dominant group norms (or descriptive norms) as guiding rules of behavior. Research on humans has also shown that social norms have the power to influence what others do.[31] In the judgment and decision-making research, this observation has come to be known as the bandwagon effect. The power of this bias has also been demonstrated in the field of charitable giving. In fact, people have been shown to donate more, or to exhibit an increased likelihood to donate, when they perceived donating to charity as the social norm or the default choice.[32] Therefore, the fact that many people become increasingly in favor of donating to ineffective options, then society will see the creation of a norm for people to give ineffectively.[10] As a result, people rely more strongly on their intuitions[33] which lead them to choosing to give ineffectively simply because they know that most others would do the same thing.[10]

Motivational obstacles

Subjective preferences

People often prioritize giving to charities that align with their subjectively preferred causes.[20] Commonly, people believe charity to be a subjective decision which should not be motivated by numbers, but by care for the cause. This aligns with the theory of warm-glow giving originally proposed by the economist James Andreoni. According to Andreoni (1990), individuals gain satisfaction from the act of giving but are not concerned about the benefits generated by their act.[34][20]

Narrow moral circle

Moral circle expansion is the concept of increasing one's number and kind of subjects deserving of moral concern over time.[35] The establishment of one's moral circle depends on spatial, biological, and temporal proximity.[35][4] For instance, many donors in WEIRD countries tend to favor charities that conduct work within their respective geographical boundaries.[2] In terms of biological distance, people favor donating money to help humans instead of animals, even in cases when animals can have equal cognitive and suffering capacities.[36][37] The idea of temporal proximity relates to people's tendency to prefer helping current generations over future ones.[38][4]

Scope neglect (insensitivity)

Scope neglect (or scope insensitivity) is the idea that people are numb to the number of victims in large, high-stake humanitarian situations.[39][40] Some research has compared this cognitive bias to the economic concept of diminishing marginal utility wherein people demonstrate a decreasing non-linear concern for individuals as the number of people increases.[40]

Epistemic obstacles

Overhead aversion

Donors are averse to giving charities that devote a lot of their expenses to administration[41] or running costs.[9][15] Several studies have demonstrated the ubiquitous effect of overhead aversion which is commonly attributed to people's conflation between overhead spending and charity cost-effectiveness (or impact).[41][9][15] Furthermore, some have argued that when donors learn that a charity uses their donation to fund running costs, donors experience a diminished feeling of warm-glow,[34] which is a significant driver of donation behavior.[41]

Quantifiability scepticism

Demonstration of quality-adjusted life years (QALYs) for two individuals. Individual A (who did not receive an intervention) has fewer QALYs than individual B (who received an intervention).

Intangible outcomes (such as health interventions, charity effectiveness) are hard to quantify, and many people doubt that they can every be quantified and compared.[4] However, in disciplines such as health economics, health outcomes and interventions are quantified and evaluated using metrics such as quality-adjusted life years (QALYs).[42] In a similar vein, happiness economists have developed the concept of wellbeing-years (WELLBYs) which evaluates effectiveness in terms of life-years lived up to full life satisfaction.[43] Put simply, a WELLBY is given by:Where is the number of lives remaining from the region's life expectancy and is the change in life satisfaction expected to result from a particular action or intervention.[44] Thus, charity cost-effectiveness analyses use a number of different measures grounded in academic research to quantify their impact, allowing direct comparisons of charities that address multiple causes.[4]

Ignorance about more effective options

The effective altruism movement does substantial work on identifying the world's most effective charities through charity evaluators such as GiveWell, Giving What We Can, and Animal Charity Evaluators. However, many people are unaware of these organizations and the charities they evaluate,[15] and are strongly driven by emotional responses when estimating the effectiveness of a charity;[15] choosing instead to prioritize those causes to which they have a personal connection.[20]

See also

References

  1. ^ Pummer, Theron; MacAskill, William (June 2020). "Effective altruism". In LaFollette, Hugh (ed.). International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, New Jersey: John Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–9. doi:10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee883. ISBN 9781444367072. OCLC 829259960. S2CID 241220220.
  2. ^ a b c "Heuristics and Biases in Charity", The Science of Giving, Psychology Press, pp. 233–254, 2011-01-19, doi:10.4324/9780203865972-24, ISBN 978-0-203-86597-2
  3. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Burum, Bethany; Nowak, Martin A.; Hoffman, Moshe (December 2020). "An evolutionary explanation for ineffective altruism". Nature Human Behaviour. 4 (12): 1245–1257. doi:10.1038/s41562-020-00950-4. ISSN 2397-3374. PMID 33046859. S2CID 222318993.
  4. ^ a b c d e f g Caviola, Lucius; Schubert, Stefan; Greene, Joshua D. (July 2021). "The Psychology of (In)Effective Altruism". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 25 (7): 596–607. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2021.03.015. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 33962844.
  5. ^ a b "CAF World Giving Index 2023" (PDF). Charities Aid Foundation (CAF). 2023. Retrieved 14 November 2023.
  6. ^ "World Giving Index 2022: A global view of giving trends" (PDF). Charities Aid Foundation (CAF). 2022. Retrieved 10 November 2023.
  7. ^ Giving USA 2020: The Annual Report on Philanthropy for the Year 2019. Giving USA Foundation. 2020. ISBN 9780998746654.
  8. ^ Lewis, Joshua; Small, Deborah (2018). Gershoff, Andrew; Kozinets, Robert; White, Tiffany (eds.). "Ineffective Altruism: Giving Less When Donations Do More". NA - Advances in Consumer Research. 46. Duluth, Minnesota: Association for Consumer Research: 194–198.
  9. ^ a b c Caviola, Lucius; Faulmüller, Nadira; Everett, Jim A. C.; Savulescu, Julian; Kahane, Guy (July 2014). "The evaluability bias in charitable giving: Saving administration costs or saving lives?". Judgment and Decision Making. 9 (4): 303–315. doi:10.1017/S1930297500006185. S2CID 18730753. ProQuest 1548669952.
  10. ^ a b c d e f g Jaeger, Bastian; van Vugt, Mark (April 2022). "Psychological barriers to effective altruism: An evolutionary perspective". Current Opinion in Psychology. 44: 130–134. doi:10.1016/j.copsyc.2021.09.008. PMID 34628365. S2CID 238582556 – via Elsevier Science Direct.
  11. ^ a b c Nowak, M. A. (2006). "Five rules for the evolution of cooperation". Science. 314 (5805): 1560–1563. Bibcode:2006Sci...314.1560N. doi:10.1126/science.1133755. PMC 3279745. PMID 17158317.
  12. ^ Panchanathan, Karthik; Boyd, Robert (November 2004). "Indirect reciprocity can stabilize cooperation without the second-order free rider problem". Nature. 432 (7016): 499–502. Bibcode:2004Natur.432..499P. doi:10.1038/nature02978. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 15565153. S2CID 4373929.
  13. ^ Hamilton, W. D. (September 1963). "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior". The American Naturalist. 97 (896): 354–356. doi:10.1086/497114. ISSN 0003-0147. S2CID 84216415 – via The University of Chicago Press Journals.
  14. ^ a b Darwin, C. (1859). On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, or, the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. P. F. Collier & Son.
  15. ^ a b c d e Caviola, Lucius; Schubert, Stefan; Nemirow, Jason (March 2020). "The many obstacles to effective giving". Judgment and Decision Making. 15 (2): 159–172. doi:10.1017/S1930297500007312. ISSN 1930-2975 – via CambridgeCore.
  16. ^ a b Singer, Peter (2009). The Life You Can Save: Acting Now to End World Poverty (1st ed.). United States: Random House. ISBN 978-1-4000-6710-7.
  17. ^ Aktipis, Athena; Cronk, Lee; Alcock, Joe; Ayers, Jessica D.; Baciu, Cristina; Balliet, Daniel; Boddy, Amy M.; Curry, Oliver Scott; Krems, Jaimie Arona; Muñoz, Andrés; Sullivan, Daniel; Sznycer, Daniel; Wilkinson, Gerald S.; Winfrey, Pamela (July 2018). "Understanding cooperation through fitness interdependence". Nature Human Behaviour. 2 (7): 429–431. doi:10.1038/s41562-018-0378-4. hdl:1871.1/72e0524e-788d-4f93-90f8-a6f04369a2a7. ISSN 2397-3374. PMID 31097813. S2CID 49667807.
  18. ^ Greene, Joshua (2013). Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them. New York, NY: Penguin Press. ISBN 978-0-14-312605-8.
  19. ^ a b Bloom, Paul (January 2017). "Empathy and Its Discontents". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 21 (1): 24–31. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2016.11.004. ISSN 1364-6613. PMID 27916513. S2CID 3863278 – via Elsevier Science Direct.
  20. ^ a b c d Berman, Jonathan Z.; Barasch, Alixandra; Levine, Emma E.; Small, Deborah A. (May 2018). "Impediments to Effective Altruism: The Role of Subjective Preferences in Charitable Giving". Psychological Science. 29 (5): 834–844. doi:10.1177/0956797617747648. ISSN 0956-7976. PMID 29659341. S2CID 4901791 – via Association for Psychological Science.
  21. ^ Adleberg, Toni; Surani, Faiz; GWWC, Team (May 2021). "Charity begins at home; shouldn't we solve our own problems before helping others?". Giving What We Can. Retrieved 31 October 2023.
  22. ^ Kogut, Tehila; Ritov, Ilana; Rubaltelli, Enrico; Liberman, Nira (September 2018). "How far is the suffering? The role of psychological distance and victims' identifiability in donation decisions". Judgment and Decision Making. 13 (5): 458–466. doi:10.1017/S1930297500008731. ISSN 1930-2975 – via CambridgeCore.
  23. ^ von Rueden, Christopher R.; Jaeggi, Adrian V. (2016-09-27). "Men's status and reproductive success in 33 nonindustrial societies: Effects of subsistence, marriage system, and reproductive strategy". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 113 (39): 10824–10829. Bibcode:2016PNAS..11310824V. doi:10.1073/pnas.1606800113. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 5047206. PMID 27601650.
  24. ^ Schaller, Mark; Kenrick, Douglas T.; Neel, Rebecca; Neuberg, Steven L. (June 2017). "Evolution and human motivation: A fundamental motives framework". Social and Personality Psychology Compass. 11 (6). doi:10.1111/spc3.12319. ISSN 1751-9004 – via Wiley.
  25. ^ Durkee, Patrick K.; Lukaszewski, Aaron W.; Buss, David M. (September 2020). "Psychological foundations of human status allocation". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 117 (35): 21235–21241. Bibcode:2020PNAS..11721235D. doi:10.1073/pnas.2006148117. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 7474695. PMID 32817486.
  26. ^ Ashraf, Nava; Bandiera, Oriana (May 2017). "Altruistic Capital". American Economic Review. 107 (5): 70–75. doi:10.1257/aer.p20171097. ISSN 0002-8282 – via American Economic Association.
  27. ^ Yudkin, Daniel A.; Prosser, Annayah M. B.; Crockett, Molly J. (October 2019). "Actions speak louder than outcomes in judgments of prosocial behavior". Emotion. 19 (7): 1138–1147. doi:10.1037/emo0000514. ISSN 1931-1516. PMID 30475039. S2CID 53746918.
  28. ^ Montealegre, Andres; Bush, Lance; Moss, David; Pizarro, David; Jimenez-Leal, William (2023). "Does Maximizing Good Make People Look Bad?". osf.io. Retrieved 2023-11-22.
  29. ^ Boyd, Robert; Richerson, Peter J.; Henrich, Joseph (2011-06-28). "The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 108 (Suppl 2): 10918–10925. Bibcode:2011PNAS..10810918B. doi:10.1073/pnas.1100290108. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 3131818. PMID 21690340.
  30. ^ Muthukrishna, Michael; Morgan, Thomas J. H.; Henrich, Joseph (2016-01-01). "The when and who of social learning and conformist transmission". Evolution and Human Behavior. 37 (1): 10–20. doi:10.1016/j.evolhumbehav.2015.05.004. ISSN 1090-5138.
  31. ^ Pike, Thomas W.; Laland, Kevin N. (2010-08-23). "Conformist learning in nine-spined sticklebacks' foraging decisions". Biology Letters. 6 (4): 466–468. doi:10.1098/rsbl.2009.1014. ISSN 1744-9561. PMC 2936200. PMID 20129948.
  32. ^ Everett, Jim A.C.; Caviola, Lucius; Kahane, Guy; Savulescu, Julian; Faber, Nadira S. (March 2015). "Doing good by doing nothing? The role of social norms in explaining default effects in altruistic contexts". European Journal of Social Psychology. 45 (2): 230–241. doi:10.1002/ejsp.2080. ISSN 0046-2772.
  33. ^ Croson, Rachel; Handy, Femida; Shang, Jen (June 2009). "Keeping up with the Joneses: The relationship of perceived descriptive social norms, social information, and charitable giving". Nonprofit Management and Leadership. 19 (4): 467–489. doi:10.1002/nml.232. ISSN 1048-6682.
  34. ^ a b Andreoni, James (1990). "Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving". The Economic Journal. 100 (401): 464–477. doi:10.2307/2234133. JSTOR 2234133. S2CID 6001457.
  35. ^ a b Anthis, Jacy Reese; Paez, Eze (2021-06-01). "Moral circle expansion: A promising strategy to impact the far future". Futures. 130: 102756. doi:10.1016/j.futures.2021.102756. ISSN 0016-3287.
  36. ^ Caviola, Lucius; Everett, Jim A. C.; Faber, Nadira S. (June 2019). "The moral standing of animals: Towards a psychology of speciesism". Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 116 (6): 1011–1029. doi:10.1037/pspp0000182. ISSN 1939-1315. PMID 29517258. S2CID 3818419.
  37. ^ Caviola, Lucius; Kahane, Guy; Everett, Jim A. C.; Teperman, Elliot; Savulescu, Julian; Faber, Nadira S. (May 2021). "Utilitarianism for animals, Kantianism for people? Harming animals and humans for the greater good". Journal of Experimental Psychology: General. 150 (5): 1008–1039. doi:10.1037/xge0000988. ISSN 1939-2222. PMID 33074696.
  38. ^ MacAskill, William (2022). What We Owe the Future (1st ed.). Basic Books. ISBN 978-1541618626.
  39. ^ Yudkowsky, Eliezer (13 May 2007). "Scope Insensitivity". lesswrong.com. Retrieved 16 October 2023.
  40. ^ a b Dickert, Stephan; Västfjäll, Daniel; Kleber, Janet; Slovic, Paul (September 2015). "Scope insensitivity: The limits of intuitive valuation of human lives in public policy". Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition. 4 (3): 248–255. doi:10.1016/j.jarmac.2014.09.002. ISSN 2211-369X.
  41. ^ a b c Gneezy, U.; Keenan, E. A.; Gneezy, A. (2014-10-30). "Avoiding overhead aversion in charity". Science. 346 (6209): 632–635. Bibcode:2014Sci...346..632G. doi:10.1126/science.1253932. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 25359974. S2CID 206557384.
  42. ^ Banerjee, Abhijit V.; Duflo, Esther (2011). Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty. United States: PublicAffairs. ISBN 978-1-58648-798-0.
  43. ^ De Neve, Jan-Emmanuel; Clark, Andrew E.; Krekel, Christian; Layard, Richard; O’Donnell, Gus (2020-10-05). "Taking a wellbeing years approach to policy choice". BMJ. 371: m3853. doi:10.1136/bmj.m3853. ISSN 1756-1833. PMID 33020062.
  44. ^ Treasury, HM (2021). "Wellbeing Guidance for Appraisal: Supplementary Green Book Guidance" (PDF). HM Treasury. Retrieved 11 November 2023.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)